Ernest Partridge
Some contents excerpted from Chapters Five and Six of
Conscience of a Progressive.
At the outset of my professional career in the Sixties, I
lived and worked in New York City and its suburbs. There I witnessed the
rise of libertarianism as Ayn Rand and her disciples frequently appeared on
TV, talk radio and public forums, at which I was an occasional participant.
(Rand was in fact a libertarian who rejected the label, as many
self-described “libertarians” failed to subscribe fully to her “objectivist”
catechism).
This was, at the same time, the high tide of liberalism as Lyndon Johnson’s
“Great Society” rolled through Congress and as Barry Goldwater, the
“conscience of conservatism” suffered a crushing defeat in the 1964
election.
The clash between the liberals and the libertarians generated heated and
exciting debates, whereby both contesting ideologies were refined and
clarified.
Little did the liberals suspect then that three and four decades hence,
libertarianism would become a significant player in American politics.
Today, many liberals insist (and I concur), that the ascendance of
libertarianism is the result, not of the cogency of its ideology, but of the
overwhelming financial and media resources that have promoted it.
Where liberals and libertarians meet -- and part. Libertarianism
does not fit in comfortably with either the Democrats or the Republicans,
which explains the determined, if futile, persistence of the Libertarian
Party. However, when faced with the forced choice of the lesser of two
evils, most Libertarians have sided with the Republicans.
Now that is beginning to change, as many libertarians are deserting the GOP
and joining the liberal Democrats in a fragile alliance of convenience. They
are doing so as they find their principles of minimal government, personal
autonomy, fiscal responsibility and church-state separation massively
betrayed by the theocrats and crypto-fascists that have taken control of the
Republican Party. At the same time, the Republicans continue to proclaim the
libertarian ideals of the free market and privatization, as they cut back on
government services.
The common ground between the liberals and libertarians is found in their
endorsement of personal autonomy, as articulated by John Stuart Mill: “Over
himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign.” (On
Liberty, Ch. 1). Accordingly, the libertarians (and less enthusiastically,
the liberals), oppose the criminalization of so-called “victimless crimes,”
such as prostitution, homosexuality, and “recreational” drug use, and both
insist that the government has no business interfering with a woman’s
personal decision whether or not to continue a pregnancy.
Notwithstanding this ground of common agreement, the differences between
liberalism and libertarianism are fundamental and irreconcilable.
To begin, the libertarian’s advocacy of completely unfettered individual
“sovereignty” extends to property rights and economic activity. Thus the
libertarian is steadfastly opposed to zoning restrictions or to seizure of
property by eminent domain. And the libertarian endorses, without
qualification, the unrestricted free market, confident that the summation of
individual “capitalist acts by consenting adults” (Robert Nozick) will
result in optimal results for all.
On the other hand, the liberal, while not hostile to free markets and
private property, insists that both must be regulated and occasionally be
curtailed “in the public interest.”
And why shouldn’t one extend unrestricted personal liberty to include
property and a liberty of economic activity? What justifies the liberal’s
insistence upon government regulation of the economy? The answer lies in two
principles endorsed by both liberals and libertarians. First, the “no harm
principle:” “the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised
... is to prevent harm to others." (J. S. Mill). And second, the “like
liberty principle:” “Each person is to have an equal right to the most
extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar
system of liberty for all.” (John Rawls)
The liberal will argue that the libertarian fails to recognize the full
implications of these principles, for, if he did, the libertarian would find
that an unconstrained free market results in harm to others and to a loss of
their liberties. Furthermore, unconstrained free markets are
self-eliminating, sincethey
lead to cartels and monopolies. Thus the necessity for regulation and
anti-trust laws.
The liberal’s insistence that unrestricted property rights and unregulated
free markets can be socially harmful and contrary to the public interest
leads to another fundamental and irreconcilable difference with the
libertarian:
Society and “The
Public.” Simply stated,
the libertarian denies
the existence of "society" and "the public." If this sounds
outlandish, consider the following observations by three prominent
libertarians. First, Margaret Thatcher: “There is no such thing as society –
there are individuals and there are families.” Next Ayn Rand: “There is no
such entity as ‘the public,’ since the public is merely a number of
individuals.” Finally, Frank Chodorov: “Society is a collective concept and
nothing else; it is a convenience for designating a number of people."
The implications of these pronouncements are radical in the extreme, for if
there is no such thing as “a public,” it follows that there are no “public
goods” or “public interest,” apart from summation of private goods and
interests. Moreover, if there is no society, it follows that there are no
“social problems,” there is no “social injustice,” and there are no “victims
of society.” The poor presumably choose their condition; poverty is the
result of “laziness” or, as the religious right would put it, a “sin.” There
are further implications. Since there is no such thing as a “public,”
taxation for the support of such “so-called” public institutions as
education, libraries, the arts, parks and recreation, is coercive seizure of
private property, or “theft.”
The liberal replies that this denial of the very existence of “society” and
“the public” is reductionism, plain and simple – what the Brits call
“nothing-buttery.” It is comparable to saying that Hamlet is “nothing but”
words, that Beethoven’s music is “nothing but” notes, and that the human
brain is “nothing but” cells and electro-chemical events.
Refutation of this keystone of libertarianism is simple and straightforward.
If we can cite cases in which advantages to each individual
harms the interest of all individuals,
and conversely that harm to each individual
benefits all individuals,
then, by distinguishing “each” and “all” we have demonstrated the existence
of an “all-entity,” “society,” that is distinct from a summation of “each”
individual. Because I have devoted two
chapters of my book in progress to
proving that society is more than the sum of its component members (“good
for each, bad for all,” and “bad for each, good for all”) I will let just
two examples suffice here.
Antibiotics: The over-use of antibiotics "selects" resistant
"super-bugs," decreasing the effectiveness of antibiotics for all. But just
one more anti-biotic prescription for a trivial, "self-limiting" bronchial
infection won't make a significant difference "in general," while it will
clearly benefit the individual patient. But multiply that individual
doctor's prescription by the millions, and we have a serious problem. "Good
for each patient, bad for the general population." The solution: restrict
the use of antibiotics to the seriously ill. Individuals with trivial and
non-life-threatening ailments must “tough it out.” “Bad for each, good for
all.”
Traffic laws: We all agree
that traffic laws can be a nuisance. But if you believe that traffic lights
constrain your freedom of movement, try to drive across Manhattan during a
power outage! In the blackouts of 1965 and 1977 in the eastern United States
and Canada, traffic began to move only after the police and a few citizen
volunteers stood at the intersections and directed traffic. (I was in
Manhattan during both events). The decision of each driver to accept
constraints worked to the advantage of all. So too with the traffic lights
and stop signs that we encounter daily. We are all freer to move about only because
we have collectively agreed to restrict our individual freedom of movement.
“Bad for each, good for all.”
To sum up: “society” is not, as the libertarians would have us believe,
simply a physical location where autonomous private individuals “do their
own thing,” from which activity somehow, “as if by an invisible hand” (Adam
Smith), benefits for all accrue without foresight or planning. On the
contrary, the liberal insists, a society is more than the sum of its
individual parts. A society is, as John Rawls puts it, “a cooperative
venture for mutual advantage [which] makes possible a better life for all
than any would have if each were to live solely by his own efforts.” As the
anti-biotics and traffic examples illustrate, common goods are achieved
through individual constraint and sacrifice. “ Bad for each, good for all.”
Conversely, unconstrained self-serving behavior by each individual can harm
society as a whole. “Good for Each, Bad for all.”
The liberal does not deny that self-serving individual behavior, for example
by scientists, entrepreneurs and artists, often or even usually results in
benefits for all. (“Good for each, good for all”). Instead, the liberal
insists that this is not a universal rule. In innumerable instances, such as
the two presented above, it can be clearly shown that social benefit
requires individual constraint and sacrifice.
Concerning Rights. The
libertarian recognizes three fundamental rights: to life, liberty and
property. All three are “negative rights” – rights to non-interference by
others. From these rights are derived the only legitimate functions of
government: protection of life, liberty and property from within (the
police), from abroad (the military), and the adjudication of property
disputes (the civil courts). And because these are the only legitimate
functions of government, all other existing government services and property
should be privatized.
The liberal, while accepting the libertarian triad of negative rights, also
proclaims the citizens’ “positive rights” – to an education, to employment
with a living wage and safe working conditions, to a clean and safe
environment, etc. These rights arise from the fact that the liberal, unlike
the libertarian, recognizes social benefits and public interests.
Communities flourish, the liberal insists, when they include an educated
work force, when the citizens are assured that their basic needs for
livelihood and health-care are met, and when the citizens share the
conviction that the
society istheir society and
that they have a role in its governance. And because the communal activity
produces more wealth than would be obtained by the sum of individual
efforts, members of the community have positive rights to a share of that
wealth, and to community assistance in case of misfortune.
Accordingly, Ayn Rand’s ubermensch,
John Galt, is a fantasy. There is no fully “self-made man,” morally free of
all responsibility and obligation to the society that nurtured him and
sustains him. On the contrary, as the nineteenth century sociologist, W. T.
Hobhouse observed:
The organizer of industry who thinks
he has 'made' himself and his business has found a whole social system
ready to his hand in skilled workers, machinery, a market, peace and
order -- a vast apparatus and a pervasive atmosphere, the joint creation
of millions of men and scores of generations. Take away the whole social
factor, and we have not Robinson Crusoe with his salvage from the wreck
and his acquired knowledge, but the native savage living on roots,
berries and vermin.
Moral perspective. As we
have noted above, human rights are at the center of both the libertarian and
the liberal ideologies. And from this pivotal center, the two ideologies
diverge.
They diverge because libertarians and progressives articulate their moral
and political philosophies from radically different perspectives.
-
The Libertarian: From
the point of view of the individual (“the egocentric point of view”).
“Good for each.” From this perspective, the individual is enjoined to “
live for his own sake, neither sacrificing himself to others nor
sacrificing others to himself.” (Ayn Rand).
-
The Progressive: From
the perspective of an unbiased benevolent spectator of society (“the
moral point of view”). “Good for all.”
Thus the libertarian (who, recall, denies
the very existence of “society”) advocates the maximum liberty for each
individual. The liberal, on the other hand, seeks to maximize the amount of
liberty extant in the society.
The liberal argues that, paradoxically, the egocentric point of view can not
accomplish the libertarian goal of maximizing individual liberty. It fails,
because individual liberties, and especially the liberties enjoyed by the
privileged, powerful and wealthy, constrain the liberties and diminish the
welfare of others. In other words, they violate the "no harm" and "like
liberty" principles." “Good for each, bad for all.”
Furthermore, the libertarian’s egocentric perspective fails because
political and economic problems are not problems of individuals, they are
problems of groups (i.e., of “all”), and therefore the interests of all affected
individuals must be taken into account. The liberal proposes that these
interests are best “taken into account,” fairly and equally, from the
perspective of a hypothetical individual who is unbiased and benevolent –
seeking the best result for all while respecting the inalienable rights of
each.
In fact, no such neutral observer is actually necessary, for each moral
agent, and the agent’s surrogate, the government, is quite capable of
adopting the point of view of the hypothetical “unbiased benevolent
observer.” Indeed, we did just that as we found solutions to the
aforementioned problems, the use of antibiotics and traffic control, whereby
constraints upon each resulted in benefits to all. There we found that the
astute moral agent would, as a “the unbiased benevolent observer,” perceive
that all would benefit from antibiotics if these drugs were not prescribed
for inconsequential ailments, and the same observer would conclude that the
freedom of vehicular movement for all is enhance by imposing constraining
rules upon each.
The perspective of the “unbiased neutral observer” has a name – in fact,
numerous names, since it is one of the most familiar concepts in the history
of political theory and moral philosophy: “the impartial spectator” (Adam
Smith), “the ideal observer” (John Stuart Mill), “the general will”
(Rousseau), “the view from nowhere” (Thomas Nagel), “the original position”
(John Rawls), and my personal favorite, "the
moral point of view" (Kurt
Baier, Kai Nielsen and many more).
And who or what is most appropriately entitled to adopt the perspective of
the “unbiased, benevolent observer?” What else than an agency selected and
acting by the consent of the people, an agency that enacts and administers
laws to the benefit of all, an agency constituted to “establish Justice,
insure domestic tranquility, provide for the common defense, promote the
general welfare, and secure the blessings of liberty.”
That agency has a name: “democratic government.” And in case you didn’t
notice, the above quotation is from the Preamble to the Constitution of the
United States.
The Menace of Libertarianism. Libertarianism appears, at last, to be
succumbing to the consequences of its own "success." We are discovering at
last that this stark and simple theorycannot
accommodate itself to social and political realities. For there is, in
fact, such a thing as a “society,” and there is a “public interest.” Social
problems are not solved, and social justice is not obtained, through the
egocentric point of view -- the pursuit of self-interest by each individual
in a mythical “free market.” Instead, as we have seen and as the liberal
insists, the public interest is best perceived through the “moral point of
view” – the perspective of the unbiased benevolent observer” of society.
Libertarianism, a fascinating intellectual diversion and challenge in the
sixties, has become a menace in this new century. The denial of the very
existence of society and the public interest is an invitation to chaos,
which must result in the unraveling of civilization and the just society,
and in its place a
government of, by, and for the privileged, the powerful, and the wealthy.
Proving libertarianism wrong and immoral is not difficult. However, removing
the libertarians from power and repairing the damage that they have caused,
will be horrendously difficult.
And there is no guarantee that these efforts will succeed.
A Postscript: Due to space constraints, I have
been obliged to make several bold claims without supporting arguments.
However, I have defended most of these claims at length elsewhere, in
works that I have linked in this essay. There the reader will also find
citations for the quotations in this essay. EP.
Copyright 2007 by Ernest Partridge