Environmental Ethics
and Public Policy
Ernest Partridge, Ph.D
www.igc.org/gadfly


HOME PAGE                             
                                                   
Editorials 
    Philosophy and Religion
    Ethics, Moral Issues, the Law
    The Environment
    Economics
    Education
    Science

On Politics
    The Crisis
    Foreign Relations, War, Peace
    The Media
    The Elections
    Civil Liberties and Dissent
    Republicans & the Right
    Democrats & the Left
    Lies, Propaganda & Corruption
    Culture War & Religious Right
    Coup d'Etat, 2000

Published Papers

Unpublished Papers

Reviews, Lectures, etc.    

Internet Publications

Jottings

Lecture Topics

Conscience of a Progressive
    (A Book in Progress)

A Dim View of Libertarianism

Rawls and the Duty to Posterity
    (Doctoral Dissertation)

The Ecology Project

For Environmental Educators

The Russian Environment

NO MO PO MO
    (Critiques of Post Modernism)

Notes from the Brink
    (Peace Studies)

The Gadfly's Bio Sketch

The Gadfly's Publications

The Online Gadfly: Editorial Policy
 


The Gadfly's E-Mail: gadfly@igc.org


Classical Guitar:
"The Other Profession
"

 

 

 

SHOULD WE SEEK A BETTER FUTURE? 


Combining: "Should We Seek a Better Future?"
Ethics and the Environment,
3(1): 81-95 -- Summer, 1998

and

"The Future -- For Better or Worse,"
Environmental Values 11, 2002, pp 79-80.

Revised and Extended, March 2007 and February 2013


A brief and early version of this paper was presented at the 1982 Meeting of the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association in March, 1982.  It has undergone refinements in several subsequent presentations, and was published in Ethics and the Environment in 1998.   In 2002 parts of a later publication, "The Future -- For Better or Worse" (Environmental Values, vol. 11) were incorporated into the paper.   I am grateful to Prof.  J.  Michael Russell, for his useful comments at the APA meeting, and to Christopher Morris, Thomas Schwartz, and the late Gregory Kavka, all of whom have responded helpfully to the manuscript as it has progressed.  This essay is dedicated to the memory of Prof.  Kavka, whose untimely death at the height of his philosophical powers and productivity, is an inconsolable loss to his profession and to his friends.

 

Abstract

The radical contingencies attending human reproduction indicate that attempts to improve the living conditions of future generations results in generations populated by different individuals than would otherwise have been born.  This remarkable consequence challenges the widespread belief that the present generation has responsibilities to its remote successors.  I contend, first, that while the radical genetic contingency and epistemological indeterminacy of future persons absolves us of obligations to act "in behalf of" them as individuals, this moral absolution does not entail a permission to disregard entirely the remote consequences of our policies.  Since relevant moral principles bind us to persons in general, not to particular individuals, we remain obligated to improve the life prospects of whatever individuals eventually come into being.  Second, I suggest that by applying an analogous argument within the lives of persons rather than to the long history of civilization, we arrive at the morally repugnant result of negating obligations to contemporary persons.  Conversely, the condition of continuity which affords moral legitimacy to personal obligations among contemporaries likewise entails moral responsibility for the life conditions of distant generations. 


I

Should we seek a better future?  Few of us would deny that we should seek a better future -- for ourselves, for our friends and contemporaries, and for our children and grandchildren.  Nor shall I dispute this affirmation.  But do we have a moral obligation to attempt to improve the life conditions of those who will live in the distant future?  The claim that we do also enjoys widespread acceptance -- in political rhetoric, if not in practice.  But if we look closely at this question, a curious and troubling paradox emerges.  Attempts to change conditions in the remote future have the result of causing different persons to live in that future.-- persons who (qua "different persons") will lead lives that will not be "made better" than they otherwise would have been, even by successful efforts now to improve life conditions at that remotely future time.  This consideration has led some observers to question whether we have any obligations whatever to our distant descendants.  "The Future Persons Paradox" has been considered by several philosophers; among them, Robert M.  Adams, Gregory Kavka, Christopher Morris and, most prominently, Derek Parfit.(1)  Perhaps the most rigorous and unyielding statement of this paradox is that of the political scientist, Thomas Schwartz.(2)  His statement of the paradox will serve as the focus of my examination.

The paradox raised by Schwartz and the above-mentioned philosophers is of no small significance.  From some apparently compelling facts about the contingencies of human reproduction, it seems to follow that (a) no individuals can be benefited by our attempts to improve the conditions of life in the remote future.  Thus, the argument continues, (b) there is no obligation to adopt policies that will improve these conditions.  "The future persons paradox," then, is a gate which must be successfully negotiated before our generation can reasonably propose and adopt policies in behalf of the remote future -- policies such as those involving sustainable research and development, population growth, biodiversity, disposal of toxic wastes, etc.  If the paradox forces acceptance of conclusion (b), it follows that we are absolved of all moral responsibility toward the remote future.(3)  Conversely, to those who believe that we do, in fact, have obligations to our remote descendants, falls the task of demonstrating how we are to avoid conclusion (b).

My task in this paper will be to reject (b), while conceding (a).  That is to say: I will argue that we should, in fact, seek to improve the conditions of life of individuals in the remote future, even though these policies will result in different individuals living in that future, and thus, strictly speaking, that these policies will "improve" the lives of no particular individuals in that future.
 

II

As environmental scientists constantly remind us, it is apparent that we of this generation are in a position to affect profoundly the living conditions in the remote future.  On the agenda of decisions before us are such matters as nuclear technology and the disposal of nuclear wastes, the destruction of wild areas and the extinctions of wild species, global warming and other permanent alterations of the atmosphere and the oceans, the depletion of nonrenewable resources, and the continuation of unregulated population growth.  Each and all of these issues, and our abilities and inclinations to manage them, have grave and portentous implications for generations far into the remote future.

Are we not, therefore, morally obligated to act with care and concern for the welfare of those who will live in the remote future?  Thomas Schwartz believes we are not.  He writes: "We've no obligation extending indefinitely or even terribly far into the future to provide any widespread, continuing benefits to our descendants."(4)  Schwartz offers a careful, compelling and thus disquieting formal argument in support of this claim -- an argument which appears to be valid.  I shall assume that it is valid, in a strictly formal sense.  Schwartz fails to notice, however, that his (valid) formal conclusion is not equivalent to the essential contention of his paper.  It is his leap from his formal conclusion to his "general contention" that I will resist.  I will then conclude that our moral responsibilities to the distant future emerge from Schwartz' challenge essentially unmodified.(5)  

In addition I will contend that Schwartz's formally valid argument is unsound due to the untenability of a key premise

Schwartz's formal argument proceeds from four premises through five formal steps to a conclusion.  Three of the premises together explicate the concepts "obligation," "harm," and "benefit." This explication yields, in effect, what Derek Parfit, Jan Narveson, and others have called the "person affecting principle"; namely, "We should do what harms people least and benefits them the most."(6)  Essential to Schwartz's application of this principle, and the3refore to his argument, is the further assumption that moral obligation applies only to acts which alter, for better or worse, the life conditions of particular individuals.  Schwartz puts it this way: "I don't see how we can be morally required to adopt [policy] P unless we owe it to [a particular] someone to adopt P -- unless our not adopting P would, in some broad sense, wrong someone."(7)

This apparently secure interpretation of the person affecting principle will later be the focus of my criticism.  For if it found not to be a necessary condition of moral choice, then Schwartz's argument, though logically valid, will be unsound.

Schwartz's remaining premise holds that "were P not adopted, our distant descendants significantly affected by P's non-adoption would be people who would not have existed had P been adopted."(9)  While the premise may seem, at first glance, to be less obviously true than the (time-neutral) "person affecting principle" stated above, upon reflection it seems quite undeniable.  Schwartz's defense of the premise is persuasive, and if anything understates the case.

In describing what he calls "the case of the disappearing beneficiaries," Schwartz correctly points out that if any attempt is made to alter the conditions of distant future life, that same attempt will necessarily change the roster of individuals who exist in the distant future.  It is not at all difficult to see that this is the case.  Under even slightly altered conditions of life, different people meet, marry, mate, reproduce.  The paths of the alternative futures diverge at exponentially increasing rates, and within a very few generations (Schwartz says six), an entire population of "merely possible persons" is replaced by another "eventually actual" population.  Matters of the most trivial sort pull these contingencies ever further apart.  The following scene is brought to mind:

Father: "Will you look at this! It says the Congress has just voted to bury the nuclear wastes in Nevada."

Mother: "Never mind, dear, just come to bed."

The couple, let us assume, were not sufficiently distracted by the news to (ahem) forego an earlier inclination, and as a result a child was conceived a few hours later.  But this was almost certainly a different child than would have been conceived had Father not read the news, or had he stumbled, coughed, answered the phone, etc.(10)  For at each second, father's genetic deck of 200,000,000 gametes was being re-shuffled.  Multiply this contingency by over one billion sexually active males, and the contingencies that attend eventual birth of 120 million human beings each year, and I trust that the genetic case for "disappearing beneficiaries" is more than adequately made.  But there is more.  Even if (per impossible) there were more than a few (if any) genetically identical individuals in the alternative futures, their admittedly different life conditions would make these potential individuals at least as different as identical twins reared apart.(11)

Thus, to return to our original case, the decision to announce and publish a policy to bury nuclear wastes in Nevada will result in a population of entirely different individuals in the remote future, destined to be either benefited or injured by this Congressional decision.

If anything, Schwartz has grossly understated the contingencies of future populations.  For given the constant reshuffling of a billion genetic decks and the contingencies of meeting and mating, it follows that a "new cast" of future individuals enters and exits the stage of "possibility" in less than a nano-second.  Conversely, the very point of even speculating about "future particular persons" vanishes into insignificance.  Like it or not, we are reduced to dealing with indeterminate "right-bearers" and/or "utility receivers" (according to one's preferred moral theory).  With "determinacy" crushed to a powder of an infinitude of alternative possible futures, we are left only to choose among a menu of rights and/or welfare opportunities for the possible persons who (by blind luck and no possible provision on our part) win the genetic lottery and enter the eventually actual future.

Consider all this from the point of view of the present individual -- i.e., ourselves.  At every moment of our lives, we are "reshuffling" the genetic decks of our potential offspring, as well as the "decks" of everyone we physically affect, either directly or indirectly.  Thus, at every moment in our lives, each of us is obliterating several futures, and every day of our lives we are responsible for the passing of countless merely potential future individuals in and out of eventual existence.  Yet we do not worry ourselves about it (unless, like Jean Paul Sartre, we wish to make a special existential point of doing so).  Neither should we worry about it, precisely because this contingency is radically forced and indeterminate.  Being beyond the reach of rational reflection and control, it is outside the bounds of moral responsibility.

And yet, many choices regarding the future seem to be matters of moral significance -- matters involving environmental and energy policies such as those noted in the opening of this paper.  These issues appear to be morally significant not because we can affect the lives of identifiable future persons but because we can affect the quality of life that will enjoyed, or endured, by future persons -- whoever, among the infinite roster of "possibles," they may, in fact, turn out to be.

And so, like it or not, Schwartz's central premise appears to be irrefutable: Policies intended to change conditions in the remote future will (even if generally unsuccessful) result, in a very few generations, in populations of different individuals.

Grant these premises, and we arrive at Schwartz's conclusion:

C1 "We have no obligation to any of our distant descendants to adopt policy P."(12)

I suggest a slight rephrasing which would not, I am sure, alter Schwartz's intent and which might remove a significant ambiguity:

C2 We have no obligation to any individuals who will be our distant descendants to adopt P.

Why not?  Because, of course, nothing that we do will in any way alter the conditions of their lives (i.e., the lives of those eventually particular individuals).  So long as future persons are, in general, even slightly better off alive than dead, such persons born in an overcrowded, resource-depleted, cancer-ridden world would have no cause to complain of us, not even if we now have it within our power to avoid these conditions and create an abundant, secure, clean, and just civilization for the future.(13)  For if we did bring about the better future, the otherwise "unfortunates" would not exist to enjoy the "improved" conditions -- others would.  The future that results from our negligence is the only future available for them, thus we owe nothing to them.(14)

The conclusion seems wildly counter-intuitive.  Yet we are hard-pressed to avoid it.  The argument persuades Schwartz to embrace his conclusion (C1).  It persuades Parfit to reject the "person-affecting principle" which, in effect, serves as a premise to the argument.  For my part, I find Schwartz's argument to be valid.  The conclusion C1 follows from Schwartz's premises.  Moreover, the "disappearing beneficiaries premise" is correct.  Schwartz's error, I will contend, is his careless assumption that having proven C2; i.e.:

C2 We have no obligation to any individuals who are our distant descendants to adopt P.

he has also proven the claim that opened our account of his position; namely:

C3 "We have no obligation extending indefinitely or even terribly far into the future to provide any widespread, continuing benefits to our descendants."(15)

or the bolder claim, implicit therein and in his paper that:

C4 We have no moral obligations to improve the living conditions of persons who will live in the remote future. 

In short, the "validity" which I concede to Schwartz' formal argument extends only to its conclusion -- C2.  By extending his inferences beyond to C3 and C4, he has left formal validity behind.  It is here that his argument is vulnerable.

My response will be in two parts.  First, while I will concede that the radical contingency of the genetic make-up of future persons absolves us of all obligation to act "in behalf of" any remotely future individuals, I will argue that this moral absolution does not entail a moral permission to disregard entirely the remote consequences of our policies.  On the contrary, we remain as obligated as ever to enhance the welfare and life prospects of future persons.  Second I will suggest that Schwartz's argument, applied within the lives of persons rather than to the long history of civilization, leads to the repugnant conclusion that we have no long-term obligations to contemporary persons..  Furthermore, and conversely, the conditions of continuity which afford moral legitimacy to personal obligations among contemporaries likewise entail moral responsibility for the life conditions of distant generations.
 

III

The Founding Fathers Argument.  It may be helpful to view "the future persons paradox" from a different time perspective.  That paradox seems to imply that we have no obligations to our remote descendants.  But let us examine the situation from the perspective of the descendants and ask ourselves, "What were the moral requirements, if any, of our ancestors?"

Consider an example from American History.  In 1787 the Constitution of the United States was approved and signed in Philadelphia.  This document was drawn and enacted, in the words of its Preamble, in behalf of "ourselves and our posterity." While the first ten amendments to that Constitution (ratified soon thereafter) guaranteed rights and liberties to most citizens, the framers of the Constitution failed to utilize the opportunity of that convention to abolish slavery.

By Schwartz's account, present-day Americans need not be grateful that the Constitution was ratified and that they thus enjoy political liberty, for they were not "made better off" by that event.(16) For had it not been ratified, they would not exist today.  (Nor would they exist today if George Washington had sneezed or John Hancock had spilled the inkwell.) Conversely, neither should they feel regret that slavery was not abolished at that time, for no individuals born subsequently were harmed, since they would otherwise not have existed.  But even if an American citizen living today were to grant that his existence follows both from the ratification of the Bill of Rights and from the failure to abolish slavery (not to mention an infinitude of other intervening events), is he then to conclude that the founding fathers are to be, respectively, neither praised or blamed for the ultimate effects of their acts upon posterity?  The suggestion seems bizarre.  Our moral intuitions would, I think, direct us to conclude that both praise and blame might, respectively, be directed to the conveners.(17) Let's see how this might be so.

If we are to pass moral judgment upon the founding fathers, our judgment must follow the basic conditions of moral evaluation.  This means that we must "take the moral point of view," which entails, in part, that we must (a) utilize principles that are general,(18) and (b) regard ourselves as spectators, rather than directly interested individuals.  These requirements reflect the fact that notwithstanding their significant differences, most moral philosophers agree that moral principles apply to individuals by description and not denotatively; that is, due to shared general qualities and relations rather than qualities that distinguish persons as individuals.(19) In other words, moral principles are no respecters of "denotatively" particular individuals.  Rather, such principles apply generally to all persons who may fall under conditions abstractly described by the principles.(20) (Our legal tradition personifies this impartiality as a blindfolded woman with balance scales).  The task of moral judgment and evaluation is to apply general principles to particular cases.

Consider a simple example: If I owe John $10 I should pay him, not because he is John, but because John is the individual to whom I owe $10; that is to say, not because of the innumerable qualities that make him John and distinguish him from all other persons, but because this collection of qualities that is John is involved in the relationship of my having made a promise to him, and that promise falls under the rule "P should fulfill promises made to Q" (P and Q being variables, instantiated in this instance by me and John).  In other words, the recipient of my payment is identified designatively (in terms of his role with regard to me), not denotatively (in terms of the qualities and life history that identify and distinguish him).  Consider next a case of non-reciprocating duty: I should refrain from leaving broken glass on the beach, not for the "sake" of a denotatively particular beneficiary of that duty (for if I fulfill that duty, there will be no particular beneficiary), but to prevent possible harm to anyone with the general descriptive qualities of "barefoot user of that beach." Duties to the remote future resemble the latter case.

While it is quite true that people in the remote future are indeterminate as individuals, this fact hardly compromises the moral significance of our dealings with them.  Quite the contrary, the metaethical rule of impartiality ("generality"), all too violable in our dealings with contemporaries, becomes inviolable when we assess the effects of our acts and policies upon the remote future.  For, while in the former case we should disregard characteristics which distinguish particular individuals from each other, in the latter case we must do so.

From the time perspective of the ratifiers of the American Constitution, those Americans now living had no privilege of place among the infinite number of possible persons who might have lived (at our time) in the future beyond 1787.  From the moral point of view, denotatively particular persons have no preference.  Our forbearers could not foresee us, and even if they could have, they shouldn't have.  Moral rules apply to persons only if these persons have general qualities, or relations, to which these rules have application.  That we, as particular persons, eventually came to exist is an accident -- an accident that was indeterminate and indeterminable from the point of view of our ancestors.(21)

It follows from all this that if living Americans are to pass moral judgment upon the members of the Constitutional convention, they must do so from the moral point of view -- from the point of view of disinterested spectators,(22) not particularly affected individual agents.  And if they take the moral point of view, it follows that they must give our selves no place of preference among the virtually infinite other "possible persons." That being so, our ancestors, like our selves, were permitted, even required, to choose that which appeared to their best judgment to provide for the optimum future.  Now that choice has the strange result that the very fact of making it has changed the beneficiaries thereof.  (Not only that choice, but an indefinitely large number of additional events at the time and subsequently, have changed the beneficiaries.) But since the eventual beneficiaries amount to virtually 1/[infinity] of possible beneficiaries, the question of "who (individually) gets the payoff" is a question of vanishing insignificance.  Instead we are left (as were the founding fathers) with the choice between better or worse conditions in the future that will fall upon an infinitesimal fraction of the vast array of "possibles" when, with the inexorable advance of time and generations, the flux of possibility is frozen into actuality.

Thus, if, in judging our ancestors, we take the moral point of view, as we should and must if our judgments are to be moral ones, we must (a) ignore our particularity and individuality in this judgment, (b) regard our actuality as a fortunate and totally unforeseeable and unmanageable accident (as the eventual identity of our successors two hundred years hence is totally beyond our knowledge), and (c) acknowledge that our predecessors were faced with a choice of alternate futures -- a forced choice, since one or another future would come about, even if they had "done nothing" -- a choice of predictably and discriminably better or worse conditions of life.  And yet those who, like Schwartz, take the future persons paradox seriously would have us believe that given the choice, say, between a population of happy, healthy, secure, fulfilled persons, and another population of miserable individuals whose life, on the balance, is barely worth living, we have no obligation whatever to prefer one to the other.

This argument indicates, I hope, that the choice between discriminably alternative futures does have moral significance.  It has this significance even though, due to radical circumstances of time and procreation, we can not choose "person affecting" conditions of life for identifiable individuals in the remote future -- i.e., conditions of life made better for particular individuals.  We can, however, choose conditions of life, in general.  Given no opportunity to improve the lives of remotely distant individuals by affecting their lives, we nonetheless manifestly have the opportunity to choose among lives of variable quality.  It is, in fact, the only choice we have and it is a forced choice.  Given a forced choice between an indeterminate individual A who is happy and fulfilled, and a different indeterminate individual B who barely prefers life to nonexistence -- given this choice, opting for life A may directly rest upon the primary moral premise that "happiness is better than misery." I am not prepared to defend this choice, but I suggest that a demand to do so may be as "reasonable" as a demand to prove that there are other minds, that there is an external world, or that induction is based upon the uniformity of nature.  These are assumptions which, while they may intrigue philosophers, are seriously doubted by no one except the deranged.  In other words, in opting for better circumstances of life for our remote posterity, I suggest that we may have reached moral bedrock.

We arrive, then, at this moral judgment of the founding fathers at the Constitutional Convention.  If they were, as they stated, acting in behalf of their "posterity," a present-day American can meaningfully judge that the proposal at Philadelphia to amend a Bill of Rights was morally commendable and that the concurrent decision not to abolish slavery was blameworthy.  This was so, even though, had either decision been different, that individual American would not have existed today.  Returning to the original time perspective: Now we might imagine future persons saying "If, at the close of the 20th century, they had managed to adopt policies to mitigate global warming, other people would have been alive now instead of us and they would have been much healthier and happier.  It would have been a better world to live in." If their judgment is properly moral (i.e., taken from a moral point of view), they will correctly observe, "What a pity! Our ancestors did a terrible thing." But of course if we do what is "best" for their generation, these particular moral observers will not exist and, parenthetically, have no cause to regret their not coming into actual existence.
 

IV

Schwartz's argument against the obligation to our remote successors ignores, presumably for the sake of simplicity, the conditions of life of intervening generations.  I suggest that if we introduce this consideration, we do not merely complicate his argument, we might even undermine it.  This contention might be defended by an analogy which, though it may at first seem far-fetched, may at length be instructive.  It is an analogy between the history of civilization (e.g.  between present and remote generations) and the life of an individual.

The Case of the Profligate Parent: Consider the case of James, a young single parent of a two-month old boy, Richard.  James receives a small inheritance which he might place in a trust fund to support Richard's education.  However, he has other ideas.  Instead of investing the money, he buys a yacht and takes year-long trip around the world.  Richard, in the meantime, is placed in a foster home and eventually adopted by a poor family.  As a consequence, Richard is unable to attend college and, in fact, is obliged to leave high school to support himself and his adoptive family.  Had James not purchased his yacht and had he maintained custody of his son, Richard would have attended medical school and would have enjoyed a prosperous and fulfilling life as a doctor.  As it is, he will be an impoverished, unskilled laborer for the remainder of his life.  Clearly our intuitions tell us that James's course of action was grossly unfair to Richard, for in it James violated his parental responsibilities.

Now let's try a Schwartzian analysis of the case (admittedly superficial).  If James had fulfilled his obligation to Richard, then the course of Richard's life after the age of two months would have been radically different.  Not only his education, but also the influence of his neighborhood, friends, and family would have directed his life differently.  At age thirty, Richard's life prospects would have been significantly improved.  As it turned out, the thirty-year-old Richard was poorly treated and apparently had good reason to condemn James for his profligacy.  (Conversely, according to ordinary "common sense" judgment, a wretchedly poor third-world child, adopted by a comfortably-placed European or North American family, should consider himself very fortunate.(23)  Could Schwartz, with consistency, say as much?  Read on!)

But did Richard "have good reason" to condemn James?  Let's answer this question "in the Schwartzian mode." From this perspective, Richard the laborer became a different person than he would have been had he remained with his father and trained to be a doctor.  Had James done his duty, the actual Richard would never have existed.  James's selfishness was a necessary condition for the existence of Richard's individual, distinguishing personality.  Conversely, had James met his responsibilities, "Dr.  Richard" would have no cause for gratitude, since he would not have been "worse off" had he not enjoyed these benefits.  He, ("Dr.  Richard"), simply would not be.  Rather, "he" would have been a different person with the same genetic code (like identical twins raised apart).

But isn't all this is far-fetched and quite unfair to Schwartz's position?  For have I not failed to consider in this account the fact that Richard was a continuing person who, in either case, would have evolved to these contrasting conditions of life?  For as he thus evolved, he would have experienced, respectively, frustration and despair, or hope and fulfillment.  His stages of life, in either case, would have been linked and unified by the strands of memory, habit, character, aspiration, and reflection that defined his continuing self.  It is, in short, a grave error to compare these widely separated stages in his life without considering the intervening time that binds his infancy with his adulthood.  Once the intervening time is brought back into the picture, and the continuity acknowledged, the strangely concocted rationalization of his father's irresponsibility collapses. 

Therein, I believe, lies a telling argument against Schwartz's absolution of moral responsibility to remote generations.  For continuing civilizations, like continuing individuals, are linked by strands of hope and fulfillment, or of dread and frustration.  The difference is that in the case of civilizations, the conditions obtain not within a single life but within and among a collection of lives bound by the patterns of interaction and the shared traditions, values, and expectations that make the aggregate a community.  Furthermore, members of flourishing and continuing communities normally regard the life conditions and prospects of their contemporaries and successors, as well as their own life conditions and prospects, as matters of personal concern -- i.e., they normally care not simply for themselves, but also for other persons, things, places, institutions, ideals, etc.  In fact, as many have argued, an incapacity for such "self-transcending concern" (a condition variously described as "alienation" or "narcissism") might be regarded as a wretched and unenviable psychopathology.(24)

If we project a time many generations hence in which people will live under circumstances much diminished from our own, then we must assume that those who live in the intervening time will, in general, experience and endure the decline of civilized life, and due to this process of decline, they will suffer despair, anxiety, frustration, and deprivation.  The communal experience is not unlike the personal experience of an individual who suffers a decline in his health, fortune, or reputation.  Conversely, if we and our successors envisage and successfully work toward a better future, we and our successors will live with hope, enthusiasm and a sense of personal and communal fulfillment, much like a young person with promising professional and personal prospects before him.(25)

And so, just as it was wrong to subject the infant Richard to disadvantageous circumstances and prospects, so too is it wrong to set the course of succeeding generations on the path of declining expectations, when we might instead have the option of affording them opportunities for long-term fulfillment, abundance, and satisfaction.

Civilizations through history, and perhaps persons throughout their lifetimes, are like Wittgenstein's rope.  Between stages or eras, widely separated through time, there may be no linking "strands" that endure throughout, yet the continuing rope binds them together.  In an individual, memories, dispositions, habits, anticipations, aspirations come and go.  Yet these traits are integrated into a continuing and enduring personality.(26) In a civilization, the component lives come and go, and the shared traditions, ideals, and aspirations, held both individually and collectively, likewise arise, evolve, and perish (but often over several generations), just as the strands of a rope begin and end while the rope endures throughout.  And so, though we grant that the individuals who might exist in an infinitude of alternate remote futures will be entirely different individuals in each future, we still have reason to ask, regarding various futures, "How shall we get there from here?" -- i.e., "What is to be the intervening course of civilization and the life conditions therein." Just as we cannot ethically disregard the course of a life between two widely separated stages of that life, neither can we be morally indifferent to the time and circumstances that intervene between the era of our generation and that of a remote successor generation.  Just as our responsibility to a "later self" is linked to the present by the continuities that identify an individual life, so too is our responsibility to remote descendants linked by the conditions of life of intervening generations.  We are responsible, not only for the life conditions and prospects of those who will live in the remote future, but also for the intervening conditions that link our lives with their lives.  For reasons that are remarkably comparable, both the profligate parent and the profligate generation are morally blameworthy.

 

V


Finally, the Case of the Deadly Cache.
(27)  Imagine two ten-year old boys, James and John.  They were born hundreds of miles apart, at which time the parents of James had no acquaintance or association whatever with the parents of John.  Ten years later, they are next-door neighbors.

Eleven years earlier, James’ father, George, buried a container of toxic waste in his back yard, and the following night, James was conceived.  At time-present, James and John are playing in the back yard, whereupon they uncover the container and are poisoned by the toxic waste, causing serious and permanent injury to both.

According to Schwartz’s analysis, James owes his very existence to that container.  Had George taken the waste to a legal disposal site, a genetically different child, “Jenny,” would have been conceived.  Accordingly, James was not made “worse off” by his father’s negligence eleven years earlier, and thus has no cause for complaint.  On the other hand, John’s conception was totally unrelated to and independent of that act.  Thus, he does in fact have cause for complaint – he was made “worse off” by the burial.

That conclusion is intuitively bizarre on its face, and one cannot imagine any legislature or subsequent court of law recognizing a substantive difference in the moral or legal evaluation of the two cases, due to the “radical contingency” of James’ conception.  Both boys were injured due to the negligence of James’ father, though James would not have existed otherwise – another child, “Jenny,” would have been born.  But a distinction between two different lives – that of a healthy Jenny and a seriously and permanently injured James – can not be regarded as morally indifferent.

It gets worse.  Consider next this puzzle: Suppose a young father, Charles, following the birth of his child Jane, sets up a fund for the college education of all his children.  Subsequently, another child, Joan, is born.  According to Schwartz’s hypothesis, had the Charles failed to set up that account he would have harmed Jane but not Joan, for that foregone trip to the bank would have “reshuffled” his genetic deck, thus causing a different child than Joan to be born.  This consideration, however, does not apply to Jane whose birth took place before the father’s decision not to provide for both of the daughters.  Accordingly, Jane has cause for complaint, but Joan does not.  Which leads me to wonder: Does Thomas Schwartz have children, and did he, in advance of their birth, provided for their college education?  If so, what was his justification for doing so? 

This is the justification:  the hypothetical father did not provide for the future individual person, "Joan," but rather for an indeterminate "future child."  Had he stopped at a bar for a drink along the way to the bank, Joan would never exist and a genetically different child would have come along.  No matter.  That eventual child would be equally entitled to support from the fund.  And if the father failed to set up the account, both "Jane" and her indeterminate future younger sibling, would have been equally wronged. 

Put another way, by setting up the fund before Jane was born, Charles did not do so to benefit Jane, he did so to benefit "any future children."  At the time, "Jane," as an identifiable individual, was unknown and unknowable.  Only later would the individual "Jane" come along to fill that "place-marker."   Jane, as a denotatively identifiable individual, was not entitled to the fund because, strictly speaking, when the fund was established, there was no Jane.  However later on, Jane, as an individual fitting the designation "future child of Charles" was so entitled.

The same analysis applies to "the deadly cache," described above.  The negligent father, George, set up the conditions that would injure an individual, unknown and unknowable at the time, who would fit the description of "future child of George injured by the toxic waste."  Tragically, James eventually came along to fill that description. 

Apply this now to the remote future.  The activist determined to promote climate and energy policies to benefit the future, is not doing so to benefit any particular and determinate individual.  He can't, both because he cannot identify such an individual, but also, more significantly, because his activism will cause eventual people to enjoy better lives than the different people who would face the devastation due to the "business as usual" by the current generation.    He is not acting to improve the lives of particular future lives; he is acting to bring about a better future with happier, albeit different, individuals.

It appears, then, that if it is wrong to harm someone by causing injury to that person, it is equally wrong to be responsible for the existence of a life that suffers injury, even if the cause of that injury to the latter person is a sine qua non of that person’s existence. 


VI

Summing up:  Once again, the bare bones of Schwartz' argument is a conclusion following two premises:

Premise 1.    The Disappearing Beneficiaries:  Any attempt to improve the lives of remotely future persons will result in different persons existing in that future.

Premise 2.    The Person Affecting Principle:  We should do what harms people least and benefits them the most (thus affecting the welfare of particular individuals).

Conclusion:  We have no obligation to any individuals who will be our distant descendants to adopt policies designed to improve future conditions or avoid future harms.  (Note the italics).

This is, I will stipulate, a formally valid argument.  It is also sound: both premises are true. 

But this is not the conclusion that Schwartz arrives at.  Instead, he concludes "We have no moral obligations to improve the living conditions of persons who will live in the remote future."

To arrive at this conclusion, an additional premise is required:

 Premise 3.    The Person affecting principle is a necessary condition of moral obligation.

Reject this premise, and the "extended conclusion" is a non-sequitor.

Schwartz' error is his failure to recognize or acknowledge that the Person Affecting Principle, while true, is not applicable to all cases of moral obligation.  The Person Affecting Principle is an incomplete moral principle.  That is to say, (a) while it is entirely correct that it is morally praiseworthy to favorably affect (“benefit”) an actual individual life and morally blameworthy to unfavorably affect (“harm”) that life, (b) such “person-affects” do not exhaust the domain of morally significant acts.  Beyond the scope of the Person Affecting Principle are those occasions when it is in principle totally impossible to deal with identifiable individual lives, and yet one is faced with a forced choice between hypothetical populations with variable and discernable degrees of value in their lives. 

Such an occasion is precisely that which was faced by the founders of the American republic at the Constitutional Convention of 1787, as they were drafting a political charter “for ourselves and our posterity.” It is likewise the occasion faced today by the American Congress along with the governments of all industrialized states, as they face the informed consequences of their environmental policies upon future generations. 

The improvement of particular individual future lives is not the business of environmental policy.  It can't be for the simple reason that remotely future individuals are unidentifiable in the present.  So, instead, the objective of environmental policy must be to improve the prospects of those who will live in the future.  In other words, environmental policy-makers are choosing among different populations with varying life prospects for those populations.  Moreover, these are forced decisions.  Absent cosmic catastrophes (e.g., an asteroid collision) and ultimate human folly (e.g., a nuclear war), there will be future generations.  Because of the aforementioned radical indeterminacy of future populations (containing a finite number of the infinitude of unrealized “possibles”), we are today in no position to identify and to select among the individuals who will live in the future.  Instead, we have a forced choice of better or worse living conditions for whomever may live in the future – which, as Schwartz correctly points out, amounts to a choice between better and worse, albeit different, human lives.  And these remain morally significant decisions, even though they are not decisions that will alter the quality of eventual individual lives.
 


Copyright 1998, JAI Press, and 2002, The White Horse Press. 


NOTES

1.  Robert Merrihew Adams, "Existence, Self-Interest and the Problem of Evil," Nous 13 (1979), pp.  53-65.  Gregory Kavka, "The Paradox of Future Individuals," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 11 (1982): 93-122.  Christopher Morris, "Existential Limits to the Rectification of Past Wrongs," American Philosophical Quarterly, 21 (April, 1984), 175-82.  The most extensive examination of the problem is by Derek Parfit in his Reasons andPersons, Clarendon Press, Oxford (1984), especially Chapter 16.  This important book integrates ideas regarding the paradox that Parfit explored earlier in numerous influential papers.

2.  Thomas Schwartz, "Obligations to Posterity," in Obligations to Future Generations, ed.  R.  I.  Sikora and Brian Barry (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, l978), p.  3-13.  It is worth noting that while Schwartz readily embraces the implication that we have no obligations to remotely future generations, most of the above-mentioned philosophers (and additionally, myself) resist this conclusion.  Perhaps moral philosophers have an acquired tolerance for paradox that is less commonplace in other scholarly professions.

3.  Short of producing lives which are, on balance, not worth living -- a qualification which will be elaborated, below.

4.  Loc.  cit., p.  3.

5.  My failure to make this logical point clear, drew fire from two critics of an earlier version of this paper.  They complained that while I conceded that Schwartz's argument was valid, I nonetheless rejected his conclusion without identifying the flawed premise.  (As any logic student should know, if an argument is formally valid and a conclusion false, it must follow that at least one premise is false).  My dispute is not with the strictly formal conclusion of his argument, but with his re-interpretation of that argument; that, in fact, he is claiming more than his argument yielded.  (Fallacy of ignoratio elenchi).

6.  Derek Parfit, "Rights, Interests, and Possible People," Moral Problems in Medicine, ed.  Samuel Gorovitz, et.  al.  (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1976), p.  371.  Also, Parfit, Reasons and Persons, loc.  cit, Chs.  16 & 18, Jan Narveson, "Moral Problems of Population," in Ethics and Population, ed.  Michael Bayles, (Cambridge: Schenkman Publishing Co., l976), p.  73.  A recent formulation (1993) which I find to be especially direct and clear, is by Larry Temkin and reads: "One situation cannot be worse (or better) than another if there is no one for whom it is worse (or better)." "Harmful Goods, Harmless Bads," Value, Welfare, and Morality, ed.  R.  G.  Frey and Christopher W.  Morris, (New York: Cambridge, 1993), p.  290.  Strictly speaking, there is not "a" "person-affecting principle" -- there are several nuances, formulations and interpretations, even within a single work (e.g., Chapter 16 of Parfit's Reasons and Persons).  However, an exploration of these differences will serve no useful purpose in this paper.

7.  Schwartz, op.  cit., pp.  11-2.  Italics in the original.  By "P" Schwartz means "a restrictive population policy," but clearly any efficacious policy, or act, fulfills the rule.  Incidentally, although Schwartz is obviously dealing with a form of the "person-affecting principle" he does not identify it by that name, nor does he refer to any philosophers that do (e.g., Parfit and Narveson).

9.  Ibid., p.  10.

10.  For an amusing account of this "radical contingency," see Garrett Hardin, "The Semantics of Abortion," in Hardin, Stalking the Wild Taboo, 2nd edition (Los Altos: Kaufmann, l978), pp.12-3.  Reprinted in my "The Paradoxical Right to Life."  www.crisispapers.org/Editorials/right-to-life.htm .

11.  While Schwartz does not, in fact, make this point about cultural contingencies, it can only serve to strengthen his argument.

12.  Schwartz, op.  cit., p.  11.

13.  If we cause people to exist in the future in such a condition that the average rational individual would have good reason to reflect, "I wish I had never been born," then, knowing this, we would be required not to so act.  Why?  Because for the "net minus" future person it would, in fact, have been better for him if a different hypothetical person had existed.  Accordingly, there is a lower limit to the mischief that we can do -- there is, that is to say, an obligation not deliberately to cause a "net minus future." However, for future conditions above that threshold, the Future Persons Paradox remains in full force.

14.  The implications of this conclusion range from the practically significant to the bizarre.  Among the former is the suggestion by Christopher Morris that the paradox jeopardizes the claims of present persons (e.g., Afro-Americans and Native Americans) for reparations for wrongs done to their ancestors.  Morris, op.  cit.  Among the latter is Schwartz' claim that those born after World War II would "have to be stunningly altruistic to regret any of Hitler's significant actions." (Thomas Schwartz, personal correspondence to Ernest Partridge, 30 March, 1982).

15.  Schwartz, op.  cit., p.  3.

16.  Regarding this sentence, an anonymous referee asks: "Given the terms of the argument so far, shouldn't we be grateful that the Constitution was ratified, since we wouldn't have existed if it hadn't been?"  On a superficial common-sense level, he is correct: we should be "grateful."  But that common-sense view overlooks the deep paradox in Schwartz' (and others') argument.  We allegedly should be grateful to be alive, rather than -- what?  According to "the person-affecting principle," we can make useful comparisons between better and worse conditions of life, but not between a certain condition of life and never existing (as distinguished from "dead," meaning "formerly existing"), for in the latter case there is no "person" to be "affected," thus we have a "relation" without a relatum.  In other words, a propos "the person-affecting principle," the operative term in my paraphrase of Schwartz' argument is "made better off." If Schwartz is right, while we may be grateful to our contemporaries for "improvements" in our lives, the Constitutional Convention of 1787 can in no way be said to have "improved" our lives.  If all this appears weird to the reader (as it does to me), then I have made my point: the apparent plausibility of Schwartz' argument may be seriously compromised when, while retaining the terms and assumptions of his argument, we shift our time perspective from present-to-future to present-to-past.

17.  Strange to say, while the founding fathers acted in behalf of posterity in general, they did not, because they could not, act in behalf or us as particular individuals.  Thus while we might concede to our referee (see previous note) that we have (in common-sense terms) reason to be "grateful" for the adoption of the Bill of Rights and the failure to abolish slavery (not to mention an infinitude of subsequent events), we can not be "grateful to" the ratifiers, for they did not (as they could not) have intended our particular existences.

18.  Cf.  John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), p.  131-2.

19.  The most significant "distinguishing qualities" that denotatively identify an individual person are, of course, his particular genetic code and the set of events in his life-history that make up his memory and form his habits, attitudes, and dispositions -- in short, his character.  These qualities, which radically determine individuality, are utterly unknowable from the perspective of the remote past.

20.  I cannot elaborate, or even defend, the concept of "the moral point of view" without risking a fatal digression from the topic of this paper.  Suffice to say, the the notion asserts that the moral agent is obliged to make moral judgments from a perspective in which one sees oneself as one of many "players" affected by his decision, but with no advantages accruing to oneself as a result of one's unique tastes, circumstances or goals.  (Rawls's "veil of ignorance" in the Original Position captures this notion).  This is a view held in common by moral philosophers throughout history, uniting such diverse thinkers as Hume, Kant, Mill, Hare and Rawls -- indeed virtually all moral philosophers, with such notable exceptions as Nietzsche and Ayn Rand.  Even radical individualists such as the Libertarians insist that their principles apply to all persons, without discrimination.  Rawls, among others, regards this perspective as more than another "moral theory."  It is, he says, among "the formal constraints of the concept of right" -- the presupposition that defines a decision as morally entailed.  (A Theory of Justice, Harvard, 1971, pp.130-6).  For an elaboration of my position on "the moral point of view," see my "Are We Ready for an Ecological Morality?", Environmental Ethics, 4:1 (Summer, 1982); "On the Rights of Future Generations," Upstream/Downstream: Issues in Environmental Ethics, Temple University Press, 1990, and "The Moral Point of View," Chapter Six of Conscience of a Progressive (unpublished, at "The Online Gadfly") www.igc.org/gadfly/progressive/moral.htm.

21.  Not only an "accident," but an event that, from the perspective of two-hundred years ago was virtually impossible.  (Sartre and others have, of course, spilled a lake of ink over such matters as this).  On the other hand, from our perspective, our existence is a matter of total Cartesian certainty.

22.  Rawls would say "indiscriminate contractors with no knowledge of distinguishing individual qualities, preferences or circumstances" (my paraphrase).  Notwithstanding significant differences among their moral theories, the generality condition applies alike to Hare's "universal prescribers," Rawls's "rational contractors," the utilitarians' "disinterested spectators," and Kant's "moral will."

23.  This is by no means a rare event.  In fact, such adoptions are routinely reported in the popular press.  For example, see Mary Jo McConahay, "The Baby Trade," Los Angeles TIMES Magazine, December 16, 1990.

24.  See my "Why Care About the Future"" in Responsibilities to Future Generations, ed.  Ernest Partridge, (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1981).

25.  The significance of this multi-generational perspective to moral consciousness is eloquently expressed by Annette Baier:

The crucial role we fill, as moral beings, is as members of a cross-generational community, a community of beings who look before and after, who interpret the past in the light of the present, who see the future as growing out of the past, who seem themselves as members of enduring families, nations, cultures, traditions.  Perhaps we could even use Kant's language and say that it is because persons are noumenal beings that obligations to past persons and to future persons reinforce one another, that every obligation is owed by, to and toward persons as participants in a continuing process of the generation and regeneration of shared values.  From "The Rights of Past and Future Persons," in Partridge, op.  cit.  1981, p.  177.  See also Nicolai Hartmann's "Love of the Remote" in his Ethics, Vol.  2.  (London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd., 1931), p 311.  Abridged version in Partridge, op.  cit.

26.  Cf.  Derek Parfit, "Later Selves and Moral Principles," Philosophy and Personal Relations, ed.  Alan Montefiore (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, l973), pp 137-69.  My account of personality suggests Parfit's "complex view of the self." Even so, I believe that I might be able to persuade an advocate of the "simple view." While he would insist that there is a "deep strand" that unites all stages of a life, he might still concede that, as one changes through stages of life, he is notably a "different person" than he was at an earlier age.  That concession might suffice to make my point.

27.    The remainder of this essay is from the later publication, "The Future -- For Better or Worse," (Environmental Values 11, 2002, pp 79-80). 
 


Dr. Ernest Partridge is a consultant, writer and lecturer in the field of Environmental Ethics and Public Policy. He has taught Philosophy at the University of California, and in Utah, Colorado and Wisconsin. He publishes the website, "The Online Gadfly" (www.igc.org/gadfly) and co-edits the progressive website, "The Crisis Papers" (www.crisispapers.org).  Dr. Partridge can be contacted at: gadfly@igc.org .