ON THE RIGHTS OF NATURE: A POSTSCRIPT
Ernest Partridge
From the
unpublished anthology, Environmental Ethics: Perspectives and Issues,
an evolving collection first
assembled for an environmental ethics course at UC Santa
Barbara in 1980, and used until my retirement from
teaching, in Spring, 1997. For more section
introductions and original papers from that anthology,
see "For
Environmental Educators"
at this site.
|
"Mindful of the scholastic adage
that whenever you meet a contradiction you must make
a distinction, I immediately sought and found one. .
. "
William James1 |
Consider the following observations and proposals:
I am quite seriously proposing that we give
legal rights to forests, oceans, rivers and
other so-called "natural objects" in the
environment -- indeed, to the natural
environment as a whole."
Christopher Stone2
If and when . . . people succeed in
formulating moral rules respecting non-human
entities, it maybe contended that these entities
have rights. From this standpoint the meaning of
the rights of rocks is that we should be
ethical, not merely economic, in our treatment
of rocks.
Roderick Nash3
It is absurd to say that rocks can have
rights . . . because rocks belong to a
category of entities of whom rights cannot
meaningfully be predicated.
Joel Feinberg4
It would seem that there is a fundamental and substantive
disagreement here between Stone and Nash on the one side, and
Feinberg on the other. But might not the contestants be firing
past, not at, each other? That will be the essential contention
of this analysis. To abandon the military metaphor and write
literally, I suggest that the dispute is less substantive than
it is conceptual. If so, then a resolution of the apparent
dispute lies not in a citation of facts (since it seems that
none are, or can be, in dispute here) but in a clarification and
elaboration of concepts. Following Ludwig Wittgenstein's apt
phrasing, the task is no to to "solve" the problem, but to "dis-solve"
it -- that is, to identify it as a "non- problem."
We accomplish this "dissolution," I think, by following
William James' advice: We look for distinctions. If we do, I
believe that we will find that Feinberg, Nash and Stone each
mean, by "rights," at least three different concepts, and quite
possibly more. In a word, the philosopher, the historian and the
legal scholar are "talking past" each other (and thus,
parenthetically, it might be logically possible to agree with
all of them). Indeed, the "conceptual map" may be more
complicated still, for I sense that there are several
distinct senses of "rights" distributed in at least two basic
categories. These two fundamental categories, with which we
begin our analysis, are "legal rights" and moral
rights.
"Legal right" might be defined as
"powers, privileges, opportunities and immunities
that are explicitly enacted, codified, protected and
enforced by the power of the state."
Stone's definition spells out the operational
implication of such a conception. He writes: "an entity cannot
be said to hold a legal right unless and until some
authoritative body is prepared to give some amount of
review to actions that are colorably inconsistent with that
right." To this definition, Stone adds three criteria which, he
says:
go towards making a thing count jurally --
to have a legally recognized worth and dignity in its
own right, and not merely to serve as a means to benefit
"us" (however the contemporary group of
rights-holders may be). They are, first, that the thing
can institute legal actions at its behest;
second, that in determining the granting of legal
relief, the court must take injury to it into
account; and, third, that relief must run to the benefit of it.5
With this definition of "legal rights" on record, the
definition of "moral rights" is readily accessible. Such rights
are:
Powers, privileges, opportunities and immunities
that are founded upon basic moral principles and are
supported by cogent rational arguments.
The above is a definition of normative moral rights
("rights" that people should or do have, by moral
principle). Descriptive moral rights can be defined
simply by adding the phrase "believed to be . . . " after both
appearances of the verb "are" in the above definition. This
qualification allows for the fact that a belief about
rights is a thing apart from a morally valid possession
of such rights. Thus, one can wrongly believe
(descriptively) that so-and-so does, or does not, in fact have a
certain morally valid (i.e., normative) right. Because
this normative/descriptive distinction can be so readily
expressed, we need say no more about it.
That legal and moral rights are distinct
is immediately apparent upon reflection. If they were not -- if
legal rights were, ipso facto, moral -- it would make no
sense to pass moral judgment upon legislation. But, of course,
it makes perfectly good sense to talk about "just laws" and
"unjust laws". Indeed, some acts of "civil disobedience" are
morally justifiable violations of immoral laws. Before the Civil
War, slaveowners in the United States had the "legal right" to
reclaim fugitive slaves (as the Supreme Court ruled in the Dred
Scott Decision of 1857). Nonetheless, the fugitive slaves had
the moral right to flee, (although, of course, they lacked at
the same time a legal right, to do so.) The concepts can be
further separated when we notice that some "legal rights" may
have very tenuous connections with morality -- e.g., "rights"
attached to the regulation of commerce or traffic, or other
matters dealing with administrative or "civil" law. Conversely,
some moral rights are, and should be, unrecognized by law.
Examples would include "rights" to courteous treatment, rights
to be spared minor nuisances or offenses, and the right not to
be betrayed or treated dishonorably by one's friends. (While
serious violations of such rights are, of course, covered by
libel and other tort laws, the remedies for minor violations are
personal, not legal. False friends are not normally taken to
court. If their infractions are deemed unforgivable, they are
"disowned" and repudiated). Only an oppressive, puritanical and
paternalistic state would insist that the Law cover all such
cases. The cost of such excess legalism in terms of the liberty
and dignity of the citizens would far exceed the benefits
thereof. (For more about the distinction between legal rights
and moral rights, see my "On the Rights of Future
Generations").
What, then, is the relevance of "moral rights" to "legal
rights"? Just this: moral precepts and moral arguments are
generally cited to support the enactment and enforcement of legal rights. Such is surely the case with Christopher
Stone's proposal that "we give legal rights to . . 'natural
objects' in the environment." Stone obviously feels that there
are good legal reasons (precedents, legal principles, practices
and concepts, etc) to support such a proposal. Yet he surely
would not do so unless he also felt that there were good moral justifications as well. Thus the "legal recognition"
and the consequent the legal protection of these natural
entities will be designed to regulate our behavior toward them,
and by so doing, it will manifest and acknowledge a public sense
of value in these entities.
The protection that Stone would extend to natural entites has
readily recognizable similarities to the legal protections
afforded individual citizens and organized groups of citizens
(such as corporations). Accordingly, Stone feels that it
would not be inappropriate in this case to borrow from the body
of civil and corporate law, the legal term used to describe the
governmental recognition and protection afforded private
citizens and groups of citizens. That term, of course, is rights.
All this legally intelligible. The law "can" (in a
descriptive sense) do many things -- some admirable and just,
some foolish, bizarre and even immoral. The law can even adopt
terms from ordinary language and transform them beyond any
meaningful application to their original contexts as, for
example, in the case of the legal designation of corporations
and (as now proposed) fetuses as "legal persons." Whether or not
the attribution of "legal" rights to inanimate natural entities
also constitutes a radical transformation of ordinary linguistic
usage is a matter of no small interest to our present
discussion. (We will return to this question shortly). But more
significant, perhaps, than the legal transformation of language
is the possibility of the legal perversion of justice.
Thus, in an autocratic regime, the Law can grant to the police
the privilege of overriding the civil rights of ordinary
citizens, and the property rights of the privileged can, by
statute, override the welfare rights of the masses. Moreover,
"the rights of nature" could, in a regime of misanthropic
environmentalists, be devised to "trump" the civil, property and
welfare rights of citizens (for example, through "zero
discharge" pollution laws, trespassing and game laws, etc.).
Such excesses could be legally enacted, of course.
But should they? Our intuitions rebel. But what reasons do we have to back up these "feelings"? With what
basis principles and rules of justification do we evaluate the
legitimate processes, functions and limits of the Law?
Here, of course, we come to the question of the philosophical,
and especially the moral, foundations of the Law. More to
the point, we come to the question of which moral rights
might underlie Stone's proposal that we extend legal
rights to natural objects. For the remainder of this paper, we
will deal with this issue of moral rights.
Clearly, Stone's essay is an exercise in both legal and moral
philosophy. Thus he offers some valuable observations on the
question of the moral status of natural objects --
specifically, upon the metaethical claim that such objects can
meaningfuly be said to have rights. Nash apparently concurs with
Stone's suggestion that natural entities both metaethically can and normatively
should be afforded rights.
Feinberg, on the other hand, states (metaethically) that it is
"absurd" to predicate "rights" to inanimate objects such as
trees and rocks. This apparent dispute can, I think, be
"dissolved" if, following James' suggestion, we carefully
distinguish and display the relevant sense of "right" at issue
here. I suspect that there are at least four such senses at
large in this debate:
-
Rights1 "Personal
Rights." These are rights of persons, due to them in
recognition of their reflective consciousnes, deliberative
rationality, moral autonomy, self-concept, moral capacities,
and other qualities that define the unique condition called
personhood (Note that bythis accouont some humana beings are
not persons, and it is logically posible for non-humans to
be persons -- e.g., extra-terresetrial aliens, possibly
dolphins, etc.).
-
Rights2 -- "Sentient Rights."
These rights apply to all beings capable of feeling
-- capable, that is, of experiencing pleasure and pain. Such
beings have, for instance, a right not to be tortured or
treated cruelly. They have this right because they can be
said to have an interest in not being hurt. ("Rights"2
are what Feinberg has in mind in his essay, "Rights of
Animals and Future Generations"6). "Higher
animals" have rights2. Persons, being
sentient, also have these rights, and still other
rights (noted above) that "merely sentient" beings do
not
have.
-
Rights3 -- "Proxy Rights"
(e.g., of corporations, of artifacts, and in some sense of
natural objects). "Proxy rights," are "fictitious" rights of
non-personal and non-sentient entities which, in fact,
represent the "conferred" rights of persons or sentient
beings. Strictly speaking, a corporation or an historic
building cannot be "hurt" -- they have no feelings or
consciousness. But "damage" to a corporation can
violate the rights of its employees and stockholders, and
damage to a building or a natural area can harm the
interests of owners or of spectators. "Proxy rights," in
short, are personal or sentient rights focused upon things,
for purposes of legal or conceptual convenience. (They are,
as it were, a kind of "moral shorthand"). Quite obviously,
"proxy rights" play an important, though probably not an
exclusive, role in Stone's proposal to give tress "legal
standing." The residue of his proposal may lie in the next
category.
-
Rights4 -- "Stewardship Rights"
(of non-sentient natural entities). These rights convey the
sense that certain natural objects are valuable in
themselves, and that this value entails duties of respect,
responsible use, or forebearance from abuse. Such thoughtful
responsible use or constraint might manifest a personal
sense of reference toward nature and its processes, an
acknowledgement of unity with nature, and an expression of a
human need to care for nature. (We have much to say about
the possible moral and philosophical grounds of "stewardship
rights" elsewhere in these readings").
Accordingly, rocks and trees may have "Rights"4 --
as do sentient animals and persons (whose natural qualities we
respect and revere). But, by definition, rocks and trees
do not have Rights1 (they are not persons) or Rights2
(they do not feel). Rocks and trees might have Rights3,
if "concern for their well-being" is, in fact, a disguised and
projected concern for the feelings of those who are interested
or who have an interest in such natural entities. The
distinction is between concern for the value of the rock or tree
"itself" (Right4) and concern for the feelings of
those who care about it (Right3).8
How are these separate senses of "rights" logicaly related to
each other? To help us understand these relationships, consider
an old and generally accepted logical rule which states that as
a term expands in its scope of application (logicians would say
"extends its denotation"), the list of qualities that define the
term (its "designation") contracts.9 For
instance, the word "animal," has a larger scope than the word
"mammal" which denotes a class of animals. Thus the term
"mammal" has all the descriptive characteristics of "animal" and
more (e.g., warm- blooded, vertebrate, etc.). In short,
the larger the class of objects a word refers to , the less can
be said, by definition, about any member of that class.
Conversely, the more that could be said about something, the
smaller the class of things about which the same can be said.
Apply this rule now to our distinct senses of "Rights." (I
will exclude rights3 from this analysis, since it
does not fit neatly into this scheme of inclusions and
exclusions). Concerning all the types of rights considered
above, we can say that these "rights" entail, on the part of
others, a moral respect, constraint and responsibility that
confines the liberty of those "others" -- i.e., restricts the
range of their morally permissible behavior. (Joel Feinberg has
noted elsewhere that rights imply duties which "carve out" the
scope of others' liberties).
And so, according to the "extended" eco-morality of a Leopold
or a Stone, or a Nash, we are not morally at liberty to do as we
please to persons, to sentient beings, to trees, to (certain)
rocks. But if we restrict the scope of application of rights
(e.g., move from Rights4 to Rights2).
qualifications are added on. Sentient beings, and persons, have
a right not to be tortured. Rocks and trees do not have such a
"right," not because we are free to "torture" them, but
becausue it makes no sense to speak literally of "torturing"
(non-sentient) rocks. Furthermore, persons can be said to
have rights of religious liberty, freedom of conscience, and
freedom of the press. Rocks, trees, dogs and cats, do not have
such rights. Not, say, because we forbid dogs and cats to
worship, but because it makes no sense to say, literally,
that these non-personal sentient beings worship. Again, as we
add qualifications to "rights," the scope of their application
contracts.
The "dispute," then, comes to this. Feinberg chooses to make
sentience a criterion (defining characteristic) of his
definition of "rights." Thus his concept is broader than
"personal rights" (Rights1), but narrower than
"stewardship rights" (Rights4). He accepts "proxy
rights" as a convenient fiction -- as a "shorthand" for
expressing a recognition of the rights of the "clients" (for
instance, corporate stockholders). Stone, like Feinberg,
apparently holds the "moral constraint" criterion to be
essential to the meaning of "rights." But, unlike Feinberg,
Stone's concept of "rights" does not include the quality of
"having an interest in avoiding pain" as essential to the
meaning of "rights." Stone's concept has fewer qualifiers
(notably, it lacks a sentience criterion) and thus has a
broader scope of application.
Who is correct? In a sense, both. Both have adopted
distinct meanings of "rights," clearly explicated their
preferred senses, and proceeded to apply these distinct concepts
of "rights" in their respective, insightful essays in
environmental ethics. The critic who accuses either Feinberg or
Stone of using the term "rights" incorrectly, is charging one or
the other with making a linguistic error -- of a failure
to recognize and to adopt conventional usage. But if this is an
error on the part of either Feinberg or Stone, it is not a
philosophical error. And it is the philosophical points,
particularly some central issues of environmental ethics, that
are of greatest interest and significance in these two essays.
As we read these essays, we can grasp early-on the intended and
divergent meanings therein of the word "rights." Given these, we
can read on with interest and gain the insights offered by these
superb scholars. And we might also sense that the apparent
dispute between them is merely verbal, and not substantive. Thus
the "problem" dissolves.
Having said all this, I must add that if "standard usage" of
the term "rights" is to count in all this (namely, the "central"
intuitive linguistic sense of informed and cultivated users of
the English Language, both in "ordinary" and, I suspect,
legal and philosophical discourse), then I would judge that
preference should be given to Feinberg's interpretation ("rights2").
While his essay is philosophically controversial, it is
nonetheless a supremely well-argued and explicated analysis of
the concept of "rights" and of the "interest theory of rights"
which supports this concept. On the other hand, Stone's
conception of "rights" has the appearance of what Israel
Scheffler calls a "programmatic definition" -- that is to say, a
"proposal" that the definition be adopted by a community
that does not presently use the term in quite this way.10
How then might our encounter with these essays by Stone and
Feinberg effect our behavior and attitudes toward trees and
other natural entities? Stone, like Leopold and Muir, may
encourage us to treat inanimate nature with greater respect and
restraint; to respect, that is, the "Rights4" of
trees, landscapes and ecosystems. But this follows, in part,
from his view of nature and man's place in it. However, the
particular choice of words adopted to describe this
responsibility, need not and should not be the central issue.
"Should trees have standing?" "Do rocks have rights?" It
depends upon what you mean by "rights." Trees and rocks do not
have personal rights or sentient rights. (That's simply true by
definition). They may in some cases have proxy rights
(representing, in fact, Rights1 and/or Rights2).
In some cases rocks and trees may have a large claim of Rights4.
In other cases, they may have a minimal claim of Rights4.
Consider some cases that might tests the extreme claim that
"rocks have rights".
Should Michelangelo have attacked a block of Florentine
marble with hammer and chisel and chipped and scraped away
everything in that block that wasn't "David"? Should the faces
of our presidents have been carved out of Black Hills granite?
Should James Watt, the Secretary of the Interior, lease out the
face of the Half Dome to the Coca-Cola Company, allowing that
firm to paint the world's largest billboard?
I confess that I can find it in my heart to forgive
Michelangelo for what he did to that marble, thought I am not
convinced that Mt. Rushmore was improved by our act of national
idolatry. As for the "profitable use" of the Half Dome, I cringe
at the very thought of that scheme, and urge you not to suggest
it to Mr. Watt.
But in none of these cases, might, or did, the rocks in
question complain of such treatment. Those rocks
wouldn't, and didn't, "care" a bit. Since rocks are utterly,
totally and permanently incapable of "caring," it follows that
they have no personal or sentient rights. Because we can be
confident that we shall never discover nervous systems or other
signs of sentience in minerals or plants, it follows that we
will never find grounds for their having such rights. This
"failure" to "recognize" personal and sentient rights of rocks
does not testify to a lack of moral development or sensitivity
on our part. The "fact" that rocks cannot be said to have such
rights follows simply from the fundamental nature of rocks and
from the logic of these concepts of "rights." Given that rocks
are inanimate, we can be as certain that they have no
Rights2 as we can be certain that no bachelors are
married and that there are no four-sided triangles.
But it does not follow from this that we are totally at
liberty to do what we wish to rocks. It does not, for example,
mean that it is not aesthetically and even morally outrageous to
paint the Coca-Cola logo on the Half Dome. To do so would
violate the rights of those who visit Yosemite Park to enjoy an
encounter with wilderness (i.e., "proxy rights" focused upon the
Half Dome). Even more, such a desecration would manifest a lack
of respect toward our natural origins and the natural context of
our lives. Such an act would testify to a meanness and arrogance
of spirit that would reflect poorly upon ourselves and our
generation, so long as the paint remained on the granite, or the
fact of the deed remained in the historical record.
Paint the Half Dome? An outrageous idea! The Half Dome should
remain as it is, untouched and magnificent, for the ages to
admire. We should leave the granite in Yosemite, the rapids in
the Grand Canyon, the Redwoods in Sequoia, and the geysers in
Yellowstone as nature has brought them to our epoch. That we
should care for and preserve these natural places "for their
sakes," manifests our recognition and appreciation of their
enduring grandeur, and of our awareness of our proportion and
placement in the context of natural time and space. The fact
that we have "received" the national parks in our time
relatively intact, testifies to the greatness of spirit of those
forebearers who set aside these natural treasures for all
posterity. Their greatness of spirit has been re-iterated by
intervening generations who have, in their time, protected this
national legacy.
Half Dome, Lava Falls, the Redwoods, Old Faithful, are parts
of the landscape of nature. A continuing resolution to protect
them are integral parts of the landscape of our mind and
culture. These landscapes, contexts, and systems, both natural
and cultural, would be demeaned and diminished by a deliberate
decision to paint the Half Dome, inundate Lava Falls, reduce the
General Sherman Tree to lawn furniture, or capture and sell the
thermal energy of Old Faithful. These places "deserve" a better
fate. They have a "Right4" not to be so abused.
Their rights are derived from a natural system that contains
as an ingredient, the possibility of conscious,
reflective, rational, cultural and spiritual life -- life that
can apprehend and be enriched by the presence of such
magnificent places.
The "rights" of natural objects are derived, not simply from
the capacity of sentient and intelligent creatures to appreciate
these objects. They derive from the natural system, the
whole, which brings forth both reflective intelligence
with its capacity to contemplate timeless magnificence and also
the objects that manifest and display this magnificence.
A decision to leave such natural objects and landscapes
undisturbed manifests, as Leopold and Stone indicate, an
extension of moral responsibility and an enrichment of moral
consciousness. Such a decision manifests a sense of moral
restraint with regard, not only to one's species or to sentient
life, or even toward inanimate objects. These eco-moralists are
correct to suggest that this extension manifests moral growth.
It is, in a word, praiseworthy. If, like Stone, one
wishes to express this extension of ethics with a similar
extension of the concept of "rights" to encompass "the rights of
rocks, trees and landscapes," we will be extending and thus
altering, along with our ethics, our concept of "rights." If we
do so, I have no complaint, so long as the morally significant
restricted senses
of "rights" remain active in our vocabulary, and available to
our moral discourse and thought, and thus, most significantly,
available as the moral and conceptual foundations of our
personal and legal rights. In any case, we must not let our
dispute about the language of morality and the law
distract us from the urgent questions of the content
thereof. We may invoke "the rights of rocks" and propose that
"trees have standing" if we wish and if we are careful to
understand the meanings and the intentions of our terms. But
whatever language we choose to use, let's keep those damned
paint pots away from the Half-Dome!
NOTES AND REFERENCES
1. William James, Pragmatism.
2. Christopher Stone, Should Trees Have Standing?,
(Los Gatos, CA:Kaufmann, 1974). p. 9. (Excerpted in this
Anthology).
3. Roderick Nash, "Do Rocks Have Rights?",
The Center
Magazine (Nov./Dec., 1977), p. 10. Nash's insistence
on "mineral liberation" receives a much gentler treatment in
this essay than I believed it deserved -- at the time of the
writing (1980) and ever since. Nash, who had an acute
personal "investment" in his theory of "the rights of rocks,"
was, at that time, a senior colleague at UC Santa Barbara who
had the future of my career in his hands. For a more candid
assessment of Nash's views on "the rights of rocks," written
shortly after my departure from UCSB, see Section IV of "Can
the Environmentalist Escape
Philosophy?"
4. Joel Feinberg, "The Rights of Animals and Unborn
Generations," Philosophy and Environmental Crisis,,
William Blackstone (ed.), (Athens: University of Georgia Press,
l974). p. 44. (Excerpted in this Anthology).
5. Stone, op. cit., p.11.
6. See pages 4 and 5 of "Environmental
Ethics: An Introduction," the introductory essay in this
collection. See also Mary Ann Warren's "On the Moral and Legal
Status of Abortion" (The Monist, 57:1, January, 1973,
page 55).
7. In Feinberg, "Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations,"
loc. cit.
8. The key to "Rights4" is the notion of the value
of the natural object itself -- the so-called "intrinsic
value" of the object. I have much more to say about this in "Values
in Nature: Is Anybody There?"
9. This is not entirely accurate. In some cases, an
additional characteristic may not affect the denotation (scope
of application). If we add to the description of "human" the
qualification "less than twenty feet tall" the scope is
unchanged. But never do scope and description vary directly.
10. Israel Scheffler, The Language of Education,
(Springfield: Thomas, 196O), p. 19.