JUSTICE TO THE FIRST AND THE LAST
Ernest Partridge
Weber State College
Ogden, Utah
Read by proxy at the Semi-Annual Meeting of the
Utah Academy of Sciences, Arts and Letters.
Utah State University, March 24, 1978.1
Abstract
In A Theory of Justice, John
Rawls notes that, in the course of history, the first generation capable
of saving for its successors receives no compensating benefits from its
predecessors, while the last generation to require savings from its
predecessors need not give in turn to its successors. Rawls is concerned
that such circumstances might be deemed unjust. (Because he believes
that such a situation is historically inevitable, Rawls does not believe
it is unjust.) I argue, on quite different grounds, that Rawls's qualms
are unfounded in that (a) no generation can be identified as the "first"
in Rawls's sense, and (b) due to resource depletion and entropy, no
generation in a civilized condition can ever be absolved of a duty to
save for its successors.
In his examination of the question of justice between generations, John
Rawls expresses concern that a continuous policy of "just savings" between
generations might be thought to be unjust to the first and last generations
in the historical sequence in which such savings would seem to be required (A
Theory of Justice, § 44).2
The first generation would be called upon to save without enjoying the
benefits of prior savings, while the last would receive without being
required to save in turn (288). Rawls sees the resolution to these apparent
injustices in the unalterable fact that there must be a beginning and an end
to the sequence. Since the circumstance is inevitable, there is no moral
issue involved. Rawls's tone, however, is one of uncertainty, as if he
expects that the problem might crop up again to trouble his theory.
It seems to me that Rawls's misgivings about just treatment of the first and
last generations are quite unfounded. In this regard, at least, Rawls's
principle of just savings faces no difficulty whatever, although his belief
that it might suggests some misconceptions in his account of justice between
generations. In this paper I will examine some interpretations of the "first
and last generations," and I will argue that in no case need they trouble
Rawls's principle of just savings. (Other aspects of Rawls's account of
"justice between generations" face serious difficulties, I believe, but
these questions are outside the scope of this particular paper.)
The First Generation. Rawls's qualms concerning the "first
generation" can, I believe, be dismissed by defending the seemingly
audacious proposal: that there never was a "first generation". But, one
might argue, if generations succeed one another in time, there must be a
first member of this sequence. I submit that there is no more reason to so
argue than to accent either alternative to the ancient schoolboy puzzle:
"Which came first, the chicken or the egg?" We can, with but a minimal
understanding of organic evolution and with a modest endowment of verbal
sophistication, comprehend that chickens and eggs evolved concomitantly and
gradually from more primitive origins; i.e., proto-fowls, reptiles, fish,
and protozoa.
So, too, with human communities. Advanced contemporary civilizations,
presently in conditions of "moderate scarcity" (and thus subject to Rawls's
“special conception of justice") were preceded by communities facing "acute
scarcity" (under the "general conception of justice"). Before that,
presumably, there was a state of barbarism, preceded by savagery, preceded
by . . . by what? At what identifiable moment in history do we locate a
"first generation" to be capable of "just savings": among the
Australopithecines?, Homo Erectus?, the first settled agricultural
villages?, before or after the invention of writing?
I submit that the "circumstances of justice" evolve continuously out of more
primitive conditions and that, while we might well identify their absence
(in a prehistoric hunting band) or their presence (in an industrial state),
we are hard-pressed to locate their emergence in any given generation. The
case is analogous with that of individual development. Most persons are
capable by the age of (say) thirty of assuming the responsibilities of
citizenship. Few five year olds have this ability. At what particular time
does a given individual acquire civic responsibility? The answer is at no
particular time! Only because of social and legal convenience (or necessity)
do we fix the age, by law, at eighteen.
Analogously, there are, in human history, generations so primitive and
savage that "just savings' are inconceivable, impossible, and thus (of
course) not required. In contrast, under most extant circumstances in
civilized societies, moral personalities feel and act upon a duty to provide
for future persons. However, it is neither possible nor necessary to
identify a specific stage of development at which a rule of "just savings"
at once applies in a hypothetical "first generation".
"The Last Generation". Rawls believes that there may be injustice in
the occasion of a "last generation" receiving "just savings" when, by
definition, it need not in turn make provision for its successors. We
immediately face a difficulty here in that the term "last generation" is
ambiguous. That is to say, the generation in question may be "final" in
three distinct senses. Two of these senses are suggested by T.S. Eliot's
lines:
This is the way the world ends
. . .
Not with a bang, but a whimper.3
The third possibility is that the
generation reaching a suitable level of affluence (i.e., supporting "the
conditions of justice") will be the "last generation" required to save,
although there will be many generations thereafter that will not face this
responsibility.
In the first two cases (i.e. the "bang scenario" and the "whimper
scenario"), the "last generations" can not properly be described as
"receiving unjustly" the savings of the predecessors, not if these
generations are the last to exist, and not if they are the last to
enjoy a sufficient material standard of living to support a civilized
condition and the circumstances of justice. While I have defended this
contention elsewhere, I am obliged by space restrictions in this paper to
set aside my supporting arguments.4
Fortunately for our purposes, Rawls does not deal either with the "bang" or
with the "whimper" scenarios, it is the third sense of the "last generation"
(call it the "utopian scenario") that he intends. Accordingly, the remainder
of my critical remarks will be directed thereto.
In Rawls's account, the "last generation" is neither the last generation to
live under the circumstances of justice, or the last generation to exist at
all. Rather, he perceives this generation as having attained sufficient
material well-being and institutional justice that no further saving is
required to advance the circumstances of justice. While Rawls is quite
explicit about this point in A Theory of Justice (287, 290), a fuller
expression thereof appears in his recent paper "Fairness to Goodness." There
he writes:
The target of the savings process is
said to be a sufficient material base for making the equal liberties
effective. Beyond this point justice requires no further accumulation of
wealth and net savings may drop to zero. Of course, it is still
necessary that social capital be preserved and the difference principle
satisfied. But this principle can be met statically; that is, it does
not enjoin a continual increase in the general level of wealth but only
that the existing (and possibly constant) social product be distributed
in a certain way. . . . Here it suffices to note that the just savings
principle does not enjoin an unending accumulation process.5
While human civilization might well
achieve a point of affluence such that no further accumulation should be
required, I can not agree that this would terminate the requirement for
future generations to make "just savings." Indeed, I will argue that, with
such an attainment, savings would have to continue to increase, just
to maintain this adequate minimum "well-ordered" state of society.
It might be useful at this point to remind ourselves just what it is that
Rawls believes should be "saved" for future generations. There are, he says,
three basic sorts of entities to be "saved":
Each generation must not only preserve
the gains of culture and civilization, and maintain intact those just
institutions that have been established, but it must also put aside in
each period of time a suitable amount of real capital accumulation. Thus
savings may take various forms from net investment in machinery and
other means of production to investment in learning and education. (285)
Rawls does not suggest, then, that the
"last generation" is totally relieved of the responsibility to "save." He
asserts only that the further amassing of material wealth drops off the list
of duties to future generations. Says Rawls: "Eventually once just
institutions are firmly established, the net accumulation required falls to
zero. At this point a society meets its duty of justice by maintaining just
institutions and preserving their material base." (287)
I submit that the "last generation" to receive "just savings" of material
wealth will, in its duty to preserve and maintain its just institutions, its
level of culture and civilization, and the given level of material
well-being, face a burden of "just savings" no less heavy than that of its
predecessors. Furthermore, it is a burden that will continue, and perhaps
increase, in perpetuity.
If my contention is correct, Rawls has erred in suggesting that there is a
"last generation," beyond which "no further saving is enjoined." (290) What
is the basis of this error? It is, I suggest, a disregard of two fundamental
and unalterable physical facts: (a) the human race lives on a finite planet
and is sustained by diminishing resources, and (b) human societies, like all
complex systems, are subject to the thermodynamic principle of entropy – the
tendency of systems to move from states of low to high probability, from
complexity to simplicity, from high to low potentiality. Let's turn first to
the problem of resources.
Consider again Rawls's suggestion that "net savings may drop to zero" once a
"sufficient material base" is achieved to maintain just institutions.6
But what, ultimately, supplies "the material base?" The economy of the
community? Or is it the Earth itself? Rawls quite correctly acknowledges
(implicitly at least), that for the circumstance of "moderate scarcity" to
obtain, some degree of civilized technology must be available -- e.g.,
metallurgy, agricultural implements, and an energy surplus sufficient to
free enough persons from food production to support complex institutions of
government, distribution, research, education, etc. Unfortunately, the
energy and material resources required to sustain civilized life are
constantly being depleted, leaving less concentrated and less accessible
deposits. The increased cost of resource development and extraction can be
offset by improved technologies, but this in turn requires greater
investments in education, research and development. The prospect may not,
however, be ultimately dismal if civilization moves toward what Kenneth
Boulding calls a "spaceship economy" based upon a recycling of material
resources. However, even this will require a perpetual import into the
economy of abundant and cheap energy.7
I will not prolong what could be an extensive discussion of this point.
Suffice it to say that, even if a "well-ordered society" is attained, the
problem of "maintaining the material base," so casually treated by Rawls,
will require constant, determined, and generous investment for the
foreseeable future if the interests of future generations are to be met.
But haven't I given myself away with that phrase "for the foreseeable
future"? May there not, in fact, be a time, however remote, when some
generation will inherit a well functioning "spaceship economy" based upon
zero population growth, a recycling of resources and nutrients, and an
inexhaustible supply of solar and fusion energy? Would this not be a "last
generation" in Rawls's sense, a generation no longer required to make
material provision for its successors? I would reply that this generation
(and its successors) might no longer be required to "save" material
resources only if they continued to make considerable investments in
maintaining the necessarily complex social and technological organizations
requisite for such a "steady-state economy." This perpetual investment in
maintenance (for the sake of future generations!) would be considerable.
Why? To answer this question, we must turn next to the concept of entropy.
Social and moral philosophers have long recognized that justice is a
fragile condition that requires constant effort to maintain. Thus, in The
Republic (Books VIII and IX), Plato described the "inevitable" downfall
of the just state. Jefferson, in a commonly quoted remark, once said that
"eternal vigilance is the price of liberty". This ancient insight was given
scientific foundation by Norberto Wiener in his brilliant little book,
The Human Use of Human Beings.8
In the book, Wiener explains that, according to the second law of
thermodynamics, viable and growing organisms and communities are capable of
maintaining and increasing their organizational complexity by drawing energy
from their environments and thus swimming against the universal stream of
entropy. Organization is maintained by "regulative feedback" whereby "effector
organs" (or institutions) advise "controlling organs" (e.g. the nervous
system, or governments) of the success or failure of control ("executive'')
messages. Of particular interest to us is the fundamental rule that the more
complex the system, the more proportional the energy that is required for
"regulative feedback" and control mechanisms to maintain the growth, or
homeostasis, of the system (i.e., to counteract entropy -- the universal
tendency toward disorder, decay, and low potentiality).
The relevance of all this to the issue of the stability and preservation of
Rawls's "well ordered society" is obvious. (Indeed, it is manifested in the
very term "well ordered"). Due to the fundamental laws of
thermodynamics, there can in principle be no time at which "no further
savings" will be required. Increasing amounts of resources and energy must
be consumed simply to maintain the systemic integrity of the
civilized condition. But is this fair to Rawls? Hasn't he granted that
organization (in "just institutions" and in civilization and culture)
must be maintained, but only that, beyond a certain point, further
accumulation of wealth need not be developed? Indeed he has. But he has
further suggested that this point in human history marks a watershed at
which a presumed drop in investments for future generations will be such
that one might raise the question of the "justice" of this "last generation"
receiving, without giving, "just savings."
I contend that there never shall be such a generation. As civilization moves
toward a utopian "well ordered" stage, based upon an adequate minimum wealth
for all (according to the difference principle), capital investments for
increasing future per capita wealth will, of course, decrease in stages to
zero. However, as this occurs, an offsetting investment must be made
in governmental, technological, educational, and other institutional means
for maintaining the order for subsequent generations. If resources continue
to be drawn from depletable sources, these "savings" will necessarily
increase and eventually no savings will be sufficient to forestall forever a
final depletion and the collapse of civilization. However, if human
civilization utilizes the few remaining decades of raw resource availability
to establish a "steady state" cyclical economy, such an economy will likely
require a quantum increase in organization and consequently a still heavier
investment in institutions, technology, and education for "regulative
feedback" In neither case is there any prospect for an end to "just
savings'. Furthermore, it could be very dangerous ever to believe otherwise!
To be sure, the term "regulative feedback" has an ominous ring to it and
raises the ever-present problem of liberty vs. control. After all, the
organization and control needed to sustain the economy and the just
institutions of Rawls's well ordered society" could evolve into another
sort of "order" quite as complex – an order of a Fascistic 'Brave New World"
such as that described by Huxley. To avoid this eventuality, considerable
investments would be required to maintain diversified, balanced, and just
controls and regulations. Such investments would include the establishment
and maintenance of institutional "checks and balances" (e.g., courts and
legal systems), social monitoring (to detect developing threats upon
individual liberties and rights), behavioral and educational research, and
an expansion of the content and efficacy of citizenship education.
In Summary. If my analyses have been successful, then some heretofore
troubling issues concerning "justice between generations" have been
dissolved. In particular, no generation which is poor but nonetheless better
off than its predecessors need be concerned that it must assume, at once,
the added and unprecedented burden of setting aside "just savings" for its
successors. In the slow process of human development, no generation is
clearly identifiable as the "first" to be capable of significant savings for
the future. At the other end of the sequence, no affluent generation will
find itself absolved of its responsibilities to save. It will not, in other
words, be in the fortuitous but undeserved position of receiving savings
from the past but being required to set none aside for the future. On the
contrary, just provision for the future is the responsibility of all
generations in whatever condition, and each generation must save, care, and
prepare for those that follow in a manner appropriate to their varying
circumstances of knowledge, capability, and resources. Were all generations
to fulfill their moral duties to the future, as alas they do not, there
would be no generations to give unfairly to the successors, or to receive
unfairly from their predecessors. In a "well ordered" historical sequence,
there are no "first" or "last" generations.
NOTES AND REFERENCES
1. At that same date, I was in San
Francisco, reading a paper, “Beyond Just Savings,” at a colloquium at the
meeting of the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association.
2. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971.
Henceforth, all references to this work will be cited within parentheses in
the body of the paper.
3. “The Hollow Men," Collected Poems: 1909-1962 (New
York: Harcourt, Brace and 'World, Inc., 1963).
4. Rawls and the Duty to Posterity, PhD Dissertation,
Univ. of Utah, 1976.
5. The Philosophical Review 84 (November, 1975), p.
545.
6. The Philosophical Review 84 (November, 1975), p.
545.
7. Kenneth Boulding, The Meaning of the Twentieth Century
(Harper: Colophon, 1965). Chapter VII. See also his "The Economics of
the Coming Spaceship Earth," The Environmental Handbook, ed. deBell
(New York: Ballantine, 1970), pp. 96-101.
8. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1954.