RAWLS AND
POSTERITY: IS THERE A BETTER WAY?1
Ernest Partridge
This is a brief version of
the essential arguments of my doctoral dissertation,
"Rawls and the
Duty to Posterity." It was originally presented to
Thomas Nagel's
NEH Summer Seminar (1977). A familiarity with the first third of
John Rawls's
"A Theory of Justice" is essential to an understanding of this
paper.
Abstract
In A Theory of Justice John Rawls
presents an account of the principles of "justice between
generations" that would be devised by his hypothetical
contractors in "the original position." While Rawls's
account is instructive and astute, I contend that it falls
short of success. Rawls's primary difficulty rests with his
"motivation assumption" that the parties are "heads of
families." Because this step violates his conditions of
universality and generality, it must be discarded. However,
this alteration leaves the parties with no apparent motive
to adopt principles of just savings for the future. Despite
this difficulty, Rawls's general theory of justice and his
views on moral psychology contain the resources for a strong
case in support of intergenerational justice. In particular,
both Rawls's discussion of moral psychology and external
psychological evidence give strong indication that healthy
individuals have a basic and generalized need for "self
transcending concern" for ideals, causes, institutions, etc.
This concern may suffice to motivate in the original
position the adoption of principles of "just provision" for
the remote future. The paper closes with an attempt to
derive such rules of "just provision" from this revised
Rawlsian perspective.
I
In his examination of "justice between generations" (#44 of
A
Theory of Justice), John Rawls seeks to determine the principles
of "just savings" for future generations that would be chosen in the
original position. He argues that consistent with the "veil of
ignorance," the parties do not know the generation to which they
belong or (by implication) the economic or social circumstances in
which they are to live. Rawls then stipulates that all the parties
belong to the same generation (whichever it is) -- a condition he
calls "the present time of entry interpretation." Concerned about
the motive for savings for the future, Rawls further stipulates that
the parties view themselves as "heads of families" who would be thus
concerned about the welfare of persons in the following generation
(and perhaps a generation beyond). Thus motivated, Rawls believes,
the parties would adopt a principle of just savings (e.g., of
capital goods, knowledge, culture, techniques and skills, etc.
(288))2 in behalf of persons in the succeeding
generations. The policies of "just savings" between adjacent
generations would, by transference, amount to justice between remote
generations.(290)
While Rawls's attempt to solve the difficulty of justice between
generations is imaginative and ingenious, it falls short of success.
As several critics have noted, it has an air of concoction about it
as strange, ad hoc assumptions are added to "fix" apparent
inconsistencies or to tie up various theoretical loose ends.
Nonetheless, there may be unutilized resources in Rawls's theory
sufficient to yield a coherent, consistent and comprehensive account
of inter generational justice.
That, in brief, is the contention of this paper. My task will
consist basically of three parts: First, I will examine the "present
time of entry interpretation" and the "heads of families condition,"
two key elements of Rawls's defense of justice between generations.
I will affirm the first and reject the second. Next, I will identify
from external sources the motivational assumption needed to assure
"just savings" for the future. (I call this assumption "the need for
self transcending concern"). I will then indicate that this needed
assumption is implicit in Rawls's own account of "self respect" -- a
"primary good" which, according to Rawls, is acknowledged in the
Original Position and serves to motivate the parties therein to
accept general principles of justice. Finally, utilizing Rawls's
model of the Original Position and "self transcendence" (presumably
an elaboration of his own motivational assumption), I will sketch an
argument in support of "just provision" -- a set of principles that
are more consistent with "justice as fairness" than Rawls's own
account of "just savings." Moreover, these revised principles of
"just provision," I shall further argue, will better meet Rawls's
own conditions of congruence (between justice and human good)
and stability (the capacity of the rule to "withstand the
strains of commitment" in actual life).
II
Generational Ignorance, Non-Reciprocity, and the Present Time
of Entry Interpretation. According to the general rules of the
original position, the parties therein know virtually nothing of
their personal circumstances beyond the veil of ignorance. It
follows, therefore, that they do not know "to which generation they
belong or, what comes to the same thing, the state of civilization
of their society." (287) The result of this condition, says Rawls,
is that the interests of all generations are equally weighed in the
original position -- all are "virtually represented." (288)
Accordingly, in the original position, the moral legislators "must
choose principles the consequences of which they are prepared to
live with whatever generation they turn out to belong to." (137) In
other words, the parties, by establishing rules for the provision of
their successors are, by implication, making provision for themselves. Since the condition of "generational ignorance" is
clearly consistent with the general rules of Rawls's original
position, we need devote little more attention to it.
"The Present Time of Entry Interpretation." One might
suppose that with no knowledge as to the generation to which he
belongs, each party in the original position might
individually belong to any generation (hereafter, "the atemporal
interpretation"). Rawls, however, does not allow so simple an
interpretation. He prefers to stipulate that all parties belong to
the same, if unknown, generation. (137, 140) He describes
this, rather cryptically, as "the present time of entry
interpretation." Thus stated, the condition seems rather clear and
straightforward. However, Rawls's presentation of it is sudden,
brief, obscure, and confusing.
To the best of my knowledge the term "present time of entry"
first appears in the section dealing with "the veil of ignorance"
(Rawls, #24). In the immediate context, Rawls indicates that it is
impossible, behind the veil of ignorance, for the parties to plan,
bargain, or conspire for their personal advantages, "since they
cannot identify themselves either by name or description." He
continues:
The one case where this conclusion fails is that of
saving. Since the persons in the original position know
that they are contemporaries [!] (taking the present time of
entry interpretation), they can favor their generation
by refusing to make any sacrifices at all for their
successors; they simply acknowledge the principle that no
one has a duty to save for posterity. Previous generations
have saved or they have not; there is nothing the parties
can now do to affect that. So in this instance the veil of
ignorance fails to secure the desired result. [My italics]
(140)3
Why this interpretation? Would not posterity's interests be
better served if the parties were understood to be members of
several indeterminate (and thus, by implication, all)
generations, past, present and future, living under "the conditions
of justice"? R. M. Hare suggests that this "atemporal
interpretation" (as we shall call it) is much to be preferred. In a
perceptive and challenging passage, Hare complains that:
[Rawls] writes as if the [parties] were not prescribing
universally (or as he would put it, "generally") in choosing
their principles of justice, but only prescribing for their
own behaviors (and possibly also for that of subsequent
generations). From this it follows that (in default of the
ad hoc restriction [to one generation?] which he
imposes) they can happily say "Let our generation, whichever
it is, consume all the world's resources and leave none for
succeeding generations." If, on the contrary, they were
prescribing universally for all men at whatever time, and
did not know at what time they were to be in the world, they
could not happily universalize this prescription; for they
would then be prescribing equally for their own
predecessors. Thus Rawls has . . . failed to avail himself
of one of the "formal constraints of the concept of right"
to which he himself has earlier drawn attention. (131) If
the [parties] do not know to what generation they belong,
and are prescribing universally for the conduct of all
generations, they will have (if they are rational) to adopt
principles of justice which maintain impartiality between
the interests of all generations. . . . That the [parties]
cannot affect the past (292) is strictly
irrelevant...4
Though Rawls nowhere directly explains why, as he puts it, "it is
best to take the present time of entry interpretation," (292) a
review of his early and crucial discussions of "the role of justice"
(#1) and "the main idea of the theory of justice" (#3) may clarify
this interpretation and provide a sketch of a justification for its
adoption. We begin, as does Rawls, with a definition of a "society"
as "a more or less self-sufficient association of persons who
in their relations to one another recognize certain rules of conduct
as binding and who for the most part act in accordance with them."
He continues:
Suppose further that these rules specify a system of
cooperation designed to advance the good of those taking
part in it. Then, although a society is a cooperative
venture for mutual advantage, it is typically marked by
a conflict as well as by an identity of interests. There is
an identity of interests since social cooperation makes
possible a better life for all than any would have if each
were to live solely by his own efforts. (4)
In a society, then, the "rules of justice" are "principles that
free and rational persons concerned to further their own interests
would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the
fundamental terms of their association." (11) (my italics, in
both quotations). The word "association" is the key here. Thus the
paradigm context of justice is a community -- an arena of reciprocating interaction among contemporaries. But if a society
of contemporaries is fundamental to the derivation of the rules of
justice, then, due to non-reciprocity of the parties in question,
"justice between generations" appears to be a virtual contradiction.
Accordingly, if rules of intergenerational justice are to be
validly derived, it would seem that they would have to be derived
from the perspective of contemporaries seeking to define "the
fundamental terms of their association." This, I presume, is the
rationale behind the "present time of entry interpretation," though
Rawls never says so directly.5
Non-Reciprocity and the Stability Problem. All moral
philosophers who deal with the posterity question must face the
inevitable and immutable condition of non-reciprocity;
namely, the fact that while early generations can deliberately
affect the life conditions of their non-concurrent successors, later
generations cannot reciprocate in kind. Voluntary action between
non- contemporaneous generations is thus unidirectional. This
circumstance raises troublesome questions of "fair return for
favors" -- i.e., "what has posterity ever done for me?"
Unfortunately, not only does the present time of entry
interpretation fail to answer the "reciprocity problem" it also,
according to Rawls, compounds the difficulties. For, as Hare
indicates, with an atemporal approach one party might not
know if a proposed rule of "savings" might entail a gain or a loss
for him vis a vis his colleagues in the original position.
Thus, from the atemporal perspective, the preferred rule of savings
would maximize the prospects and minimize the risks of each
party in the original position, which is to say, of any given
generation. In contradistinction, says Rawls, the present time of
entry interpretation puts this neat solution in jeopardy. For, since
they are contemporaries, the parties can not gain advantages by
proposing rules for their predecessors. Furthermore, since the past
is fixed and immutable, the parties "can favor their generation by
refusing to make any sacrifices at all for their successors; they
simply acknowledge the principle that no one has a duty to save for
posterity." (140)
Although he does not say so directly, Rawls seems here to be
applying his "stability criterion."6 He seems, that is,
to suggest that "the strains of commitment" will, in actual life,
undo a policy of savings devised in the original position under the
present time of entry interpretation unless additional
motivation is found, in the original position, to secure adherence
to the policy. Rawls has identified a serious problem here. His
response, as we will see, is to add the "heads of families"
condition to provide the needed motivation for saving. However,
rather than to seek an answer perhaps a better course would be to
disallow the question, (in Wittgenstein's terms: not to solve the
problem, but to dissolve it).
This is the suggestion of R. M. Hare, in the long passage just
quoted. Hare, we will recall, feels that Rawls's difficulties with
non-reciprocity result not only from the complication of the present
time of entry interpretation but also from his tendency to take the
original position too seriously and from his disregard of his own
"formal constraints on the concept of right." (#23) With less regard
for the intricacies and workings of the original position, says
Hare, and with more attention to the formal requirement of generality, most of Rawls's problems with non-reciprocity might
vanish.
Hare is quite correct, I think, to suggest that Rawls may have
may have imprudently placed more importance upon the deliberations
within the original position than the formal constraints upon it (in particular, the constraint of
generality).
However, while Hare has cogently criticized Rawls for neglecting
Rawls's own formal constraint of generality, Hare has himself
afforded little if any significance to the stability rule,
which stipulates that the parties will not accept principles of
justice that can not withstand the "strains of commitment" in actual
life. Rawls, on the other hand, astutely points out that the parties
should, in selecting principles of intergenerational justice, be
acutely concerned about the "stability" of these principles. For
unless the "stability factor" is duly accounted for in the original
position, the parties, in their condition of abstract, self-serving
rationality, may be attracted to policies of just savings that will,
in fact, turn out to be untenable in the real world where, for
instance, generations can cheat the future with apparently no
concern whatever for retribution from either the past or the future.
The question of the stability of principles challenges both the
present time of entry and the atemporal interpretations. In the
former case, as Rawls puts it, all the parties will find themselves,
in the actual world, in circumstances in which "either past
generations have saved or they have not," and nothing can be done
about it. In the atemporal condition a single party will find, in
actual life, that, at best, some of his colleagues in the
original position may have, in their time, kept their part of the
bargain to set aside "just savings." In both cases the past is
fixed. In both cases the question remains: Why should the parties in
their lifetimes (whenever they may be) be motivated to save? Why
indeed, even if past generations have fully met their "duties" to
save?
From the perspective of the original position, and detached from
the question of compliance (or "stability"), a rule of "just
savings" for the future may well appear to be rational and in the
interest of each party. Even so, Rawls's essential challenge remains
unanswered: What assurance in the original position will the parties
have that once their time arrives their predecessors will have kept
their part of the bargain? They will have no more assurance than
that they themselves will be motivated to make just provision
for the future. In the case both of forbearers and contemporaries,
the assurance that just savings will, in fact, be made rests upon
assumptions concerning the motivations of actual persons. The
parties of the original position, whether contemporaries or from all
generations, will agree to a principle of just savings only if they
have some assurance that human nature (as they know it from their
allowed fund of general information) is equipped to uphold the
principle.
Abstract Justice and Practical Justice. The contrast
between the approaches of Rawls and Hare is fundamental and should
be identified and labeled for further use. Hare seems to suggest
that we derive rules of justice entirely from "formal constraints of
the concept of right" (which Rawls identifies as generality,
universality, publicity, priority, finality, and time neutrality
(#23)), and general criteria of conceptual intelligibility, apart
from the practical question of stability; i.e., the
possibility of compliance in the conditions of ordinary life. Hare's
preferred approach to moral philosophy is analytical rather than
contractarian. Even so, a contractarian "original position" might be
devised to produce principles of justice that take no account
whatever of the stability question. (For example, one might
stipulate the condition that the parties are able, and know they are
able, to legislate that human nature be so designed to assure full
compliance with the principles). Such principles I will henceforth
call "abstract principles of justice." Hare is quite correct
to assert that abstract principles of provision for the future
follow directly from the general criteria of the concept of right,
and that such principles, being unaffected by the stability
question, are likewise unaffected by the circumstances of
non-reciprocity between generations.
In contradistinction, Rawls believes that no principle of justice
need be agreed to that has unacceptable consequences and with which
the parties can not expect compliance. (176) This qualification of
stability, added to the general conditions of "abstract
justice" noted above, yield what I will call "practical
principles of justice." It follows that "the principles of practical
justice" constitute a subset of the class of "the principles of
abstract justice." Thus, principles of saving that would clearly be
entailed in a system of "abstract" justice may become very
problematic when the "practical" question of compliance is raised.
(The distinction between "abstract justice" and "practical justice"
will prove to be of fundamental importance in sections VII and VIII
of this paper).
III
"The Heads of Families Condition." Rawls believes that if
the parties in the original position know that they are
contemporaries, they will have "no reason . . . to agree to
undertake any saving what ever" unless a motivating condition is
added to the original position. (292) Rawls's answer, we will
recall, is readily at hand: "The parties are regarded as
representing family lines, say, with ties of sentiment between
successive generations." (292) In his section dealing with "the
circumstances of justice" (#22), Rawls first presents the condition
in the following passage:
The parties are thought of as representing continuing
lines of claims, as being, so to speak, deputies for a kind
of everlasting moral agent or institution. They need not
take into account its entire life span in perpetuity, but
their goodwill stretches over at least two generations. Thus
representatives from periods adjacent in time have
overlapping interests. For example, we may think of the
parties as heads of families, and therefore as having a
desire to further the welfare of their nearest descendants.
As representatives of families their interests are opposed
as the circumstances imply. It is not necessary to think of
the parties as heads of families, although I shall generally
follow this interpretation. What is essential is that each
person in the original position should care about the
well-being of some of those in the next generation, it being
presumed that their concern is for different individuals in
each case. Moreover, for anyone in the next generation,
there is someone who cares about him in the present
generation. Thus the interests of all are looked after and,
given the veil of ignorance, the whole strand is tied
together. (128-9)7
It is crucial here to keep in mind the purpose of the
heads of families condition. In the first place, it is introduced to
motivate the parties in the original position to adopt a
principle of justice between generations. In the second place, it is
intended to assure the parties that such a principle would,
in fact, be complied with in actual life (in Rawls's terminology,
the principle would be "stable.") Thus assured, Rawls argues, the
parties in the original position would adopt a principle of just
savings.
With either the "present time of entry" or the "atemporal"
interpretation, the problems of non-reciprocity and stability persist: the living will neither suffer punishment nor
enjoy rewards from the deceased and the yet unborn, for their
policies toward posterity. When then should the living make present
sacrifices for a future that they shall never see? Rawls is quite
correct in saying that without some general motivating conditions,
the parties can not be expected to save when in actual life. With no
such expectations, the parties will adopt no ("practical")
principles of just savings. Thus, if "justice between generations"
is to be served, some motivation must be found for providing for the
remote future. Furthermore, this motivation must be basic to human
nature and universal in its manifestations, and its objects must be
desirable "whatever else maybe desired" (otherwise the condition
will reflect a particular good excluded by the veil of
ignorance, rather than a primary good acknowledged in the original
position). In short, compliance and stability must be assured or, at
the very least, feasible. To this degree, I concur with Rawls.
However, I strongly disagree with his suggestion that the sought-for
motivation is to be found in the desire of "heads of families" to
care for the well-being of identifiable persons in the next
generation. (128-9) In this section I will argue against the grounds
for this condition and will point out some of its inconsistencies
with other parts of Rawls's theory. Later I will propose, as an
alternative motivation assumption, a fundamental need for "self
transcending concern."
The Problem of Consistency. The careful and sensitive
reader may find something jarring and discordant in Rawls's "heads
of families condition." Small wonder. It cuts across a number of
basic assumptions about the general conditions in the original
position that Rawls has labored diligently to defend, explicate, and
assemble into a coherent pattern. The inconsistencies and
difficulties raised by the heads of families condition are numerous
-- too numerous to allow me to pursue more than a few in detail. It
may be useful, however, to indicate some of the more serious
difficulties.8
To begin, consider some strange juxtapositions of remarks by
Rawls himself, remarks which appear within the space of three
consecutive paragraphs (on pages 128-30 of A Theory of Justice).
First, in his most careful and extensive account of the heads of
families condition (noted above), Rawls states: "What is essential
is that each person in the original position should care about the
well-being of some of those in the next generations." (128) Yet, in
the following paragraph, Rawls writes: "A conception of justice
should not presuppose . . . extensive ties of natural sentiment."
(129) And in the paragraph following that, he states that the
circumstances of justice involve "no particular theory of human
motivation." (130) But of course, the heads of families condition is
just that.
Perhaps these bits are enough to suggest that Rawls is in
considerable difficulty here. Let's leave the samples now and turn
to a more thorough examination.
"Heads of Families" and Universality. Rawls is concerned
that the conditions in the original position, as well as the
resulting principles of justice, be coordinated (in "reflective
equilibrium") with "considered moral judgments" of ordinary
practical life. It would therefore, I think, be fair to assume that
Rawls's desire that the parties in the original position establish
rules of just savings is responsive to his recognition of a
widespread moral consensus that the needs of future generations
should be provided for. In other words, faced with this "considered
moral judgment" that the living have duties to posterity, Rawls has
attempted to fashion the conditions of the original position so that
congruent principles of justice would be chosen therein. As we have
seen, his response is to introduce the "heads of families" condition
into the original position. Unfortunately, in his attempt to
incorporate a principle of justice reflective of a widespread moral
sentiment, Rawls has chosen a motivating condition that is neither
universal, representative, nor reliably productive of the desired
motive. I will consider these points in reverse order.
First of all, Rawls suggests that persons who have the status of
"heads of families" can reliably be expected to have a "desire to
further the welfare of their nearest descendants." (128)9
Does Rawls mean to suggest here that the circumstances of being a
parent (or parent-surrogate) invariably result in care for
the well-being of "some of those in the next generation?" In most
cases, I will agree, this is so. But what of the lamentably all-too
common cases of persons who find themselves trapped, by accident,
miscalculation, or thoughtlessness, in a parental role that they do
not care for but cannot escape? The heads of families condition,
says Rawls, assumes that "for anyone in the next generation, there
is someone who cares about him in the present generation." (129) One
of the great social tragedies of our time is that this clearly is not the case in the conditions of actual life.
Even if the status of family head has the desired effect of
instilling care and concern for definite individuals in the next
generation, surely it falls far short of the scope of application
called for in the "considered moral judgment" of concern for future
persons. Would our moral sense condone a land baron's acquisition of
vast holdings for the perpetual and exclusive use of his progeny, to
the total exclusion of anyone else? (Imagine, for example,
Yellowstone Park as a forbidden and private family enclave).
"Considered moral judgment," not to mention the laws of eminent
domain, proscribe such personal aggrandizement. Yet this would seem
to be the sort of savings policy that would follow from an
importation of the motivation of family heads into the original
position. Do we wish, then, to adopt conditions in the original
position that would lead to a savings principle that favors
beneficiaries in the next generation on the basis of blood ties or
personal affection? Such bias might well be defended on the grounds
of particular life plans (i.e., "the full theory of the good"), but
surely not on the grounds of universal justice. And justice is the business of the original position.
Still another question: What of those who are
not "heads
of families?" Are they presumed not to "care about the
well-being of some of those in the next generation" -- or in
generations beyond? (128) Surely this would be an unfair
presumption. These days, many persons have chosen not to become
family heads precisely because they are concerned about the
living conditions of future generations. For example, some are aware
that they are carriers of genetic defects, while others act upon
their perceived duty not to aggravate the problem of
over-population. (In contradistinction, some individuals willingly
become heads of large families in deliberate disregard of their duty
not to burden future generations with genetic defects or with the
problem of over-population).
This leads to still another problem: What of the interests of the
childless adults? Don't they count? Are these individuals to be
morally disenfranchised? If they are not to be represented in the
original position, are they morally obligated to comply with the
principles of justice adopted therein? Will they be required to
contribute just savings (e.g., in taxes) to individuals in the next
generation with whom they have no acquaintance and for whom they
have no personal concern?10
At this point I would reiterate that there does, in fact, appear
to be a widespread "considered moral judgment" that the needs of the
future should be provided for and that future persons should not
suffer avoidable harm -- a judgment manifested in numerous newspaper
editorials and columns, political speeches, and commencement
addresses. Furthermore, Rawls is aware of this judgment and wishes
to have it reflected in the original position. However, my
fundamental question remains: Does the heads of families condition
perform its intended function? I suggest that it does not. In the
first place, it severely limits the temporal scope of concern for
the future. Similarly, it focuses concern upon a few persons in the
next generation to which the agent is tied by familial or
quasi-familial attachments, to the exclusion of virtually all other
members of that generation. Furthermore, the heads of families
condition is based upon a status that can not be reliably expected
to provide the desired motivation. Finally, and perhaps most
seriously, the condition is not universal and not
general, and thus it violates two basic formal constraints of the
concept of right (#23)
These constraints of the concept of right are applied to the
original position in the rule that "no one is able to formulate
principles especially designed to advance his own cause." (140) The
"cause" of being a family head is a particular interest exclusive
of, and perhaps in conflict with, the interests of those who, either
for selfish or altruistic reasons, choose not to assume this role.
Since the savings principle adopted in the original position is
clearly "designed to advance . . . [the] cause" of the heads of
families, the principle, and by implication the condition, are
disallowed by Rawls's own basic rules for the original position.
Accordingly, I suggest, the "considered moral judgment" that the
interests of posterity should be provided for will have to be
derived from some other combination of rules, motivating
assumptions, and admissible data in the original position.11
Our analysis of the now-rejected heads of families condition has,
I believe, furnished us with some criteria to be kept in mind as we
search for an acceptable "motivation assumption." Among these
criteria are the following: (a) the motivation assumption must be
neutral with respect to time (i.e., it should have equal prima
facie application to all generations -- cf. Rawls, #45); (b) the
motivation assumption should be applicable to all moral
personalities (i.e., "universal"); (c) it should not favor persons
identifiable by proper names or "rigged definite descriptions"
(i.e., it should be "general"); (d) the motivating assumption should
not represent an exclusive conception of the good, but should be
based upon , or derivable from, a primary good.
IV
"Self Transcendence:" A Proposal.12 We have
found that the "heads of families condition" is unacceptable in the
original position as a motive for just savings. It seems, then, that
we must find another motivation assumption. How are we to proceed?
Rawls's metaethics offers some guidance: we must, he suggests, look
to our moral sense and our "considered moral judgments." In
addition, we must draw upon general information concerning moral
psychology, economic theory, social dynamics, anthropology, history,
and so forth. Such will be the task of this section. However,
because I must search a broad and extensive field of data and
opinion, and summarize my findings in a relatively brief space, my
presentation must of necessity be superficial, impressionistic and
explicatory. Many important books and some splendid careers have
been devoted to the study, explication, and validation of the motive
of self transcendence, or of key elements thereof. I will not
pretend to add significantly to this fund of data and insight.
Rather, I will attempt to evoke in the reader a sense of recognition
of a familiar psycho- social phenomenon and hope that with this
recognition he will agree that I am denoting by "self transcendence"
a significant, fundamental, and widespread feature, both of human
moral and social experience and of human culture and history.13
The Concept of Self Transcendence. By claiming that there
is "a need for self-transcendence," I am proposing that as a result
of the psychodevelopmental sources of the self and the fundamental
dynamics of social experience, well-functioning human beings
identify with, and seek to further, the well-being, preservation,
and endurance of communities, locations, causes, artifacts,
institutions, ideals, etc., which are outside themselves and which
they hope will flourish beyond their own lifetimes. Thus we cannot
regard our decisions and the values which we hold to be restricted
to, and isolate within, ourselves.
This claim has a reverse side to it; namely, that individuals who
lack a sense of self transcendence are acutely impoverished in that
they lack, to quote Rawls, "certain fundamental attitudes and
capacities included under the notion of humanity,"14 Such
persons are said to be alienated -- both from themselves and
from their community.
"Self transcendence" describes a
class of feelings which
give rise to a variety of activities. It is no small ingredient in
the production of great works of art and literature, in the choice
of careers in public service, education, scientific research, and so
forth. In all this variety, however, there is a central, generic
motive; namely, for the self to be part of, to favorably affect, and
to acknowledge the importance of, something beyond that is not
oneself. In the foregoing account there are two aspects of self-
transcendence that are of special interest to us. First, self
transcendence is manifested in an interest in and a concern for
events and circumstances that will obtain well beyond the lifetime
of the individual. Second, the need for self transcendence is
sufficiently fundamental to human experience and motivation that it
might qualify as a primary good, and thus be relevant to the
deliberations of the parties in the original position. The
significance of self transcendence to Rawls's theory of justice and,
in particular, to his account of justice between generations now
becomes apparent. Rather than attempt a proof of the
existence and significance of self-transcendence (which I have done
elsewhere), I will briefly sketch four sources of this motive.
(a) "The Law of Import Transference." This psychological
phenomenon may thus be summarized: If a person P feels that X (e.g.,
an institution, place, organization, principle, etc.) matters to
him, P will also feel that X matters objectively and intrinsically. In other words, the significance and importance
of an object to an agent is interpreted by the agent as a quality of
the object itself. It thus follows that the well-being and
endurance of the significant object (or place, or institution, or
principle) apart from, and beyond the lifetime of, the agent becomes
a concern of and a value to the agent -- a part of his inventory of
personal interests or goods.
If, in "import transference," I have described a valid and
universal psychological trait, what bearing would this have upon the
deliberations in the original position? To begin, the veil of
ignorance would, as we know, exclude any knowledge of the transfer
of particular interest and attachments, among the parties, to
identifiable persons, places, causes or institutions. (This would
follow from the exclusion of knowledge of personal circumstances and
of personal conceptions of the Good). However, and this is
significant, if "import transference" is in fact a general law of
moral psychology, an abstract knowledge thereof would be admissible
in the original position and would likely play an important role in
the derivation of the principles of justice. And how might the law
of import transference bear upon the choice of principles? First of
all, the parties would know that in actual life their interests and
loyalties would transfer to some enduring persons, ideals,
institutions, etc., albeit they would not know which these
might be. Thus the parties would know that in actual life they
would, somehow, care about the conditions of life for generations
that would follow their own.
But this is not all. The veil of ignorance is not complete in
this regard, since the conditions in the original position offer at
least some general content to this concern for the future. For
instance, because the parties would themselves transfer
import to the principles of justice they would choose, it follows
that they would want to insure a perpetuation in actual society of
the circumstances of justice necessary for a well-ordered society
(e.g. no less than moderate scarcity, and at least mutual
disinterest. See Rawls, #22). In addition, they would want to
incorporate into their principles provision for the perpetuation and
flourishing of just institutions. All this, I submit, is ample
material with which to devise, in the original position, abstract
principles of just provision for the future.15
But would these principles of just provision be practical
principles? Does "import transference" constitute the "motivation
principle" that we seek? Can the psychological trait of import
transference be sufficiently associated with the index of primary
goods to admit it into the original position? And if the trait
suggests the adoption of a principle of just provision in the
original position, does the trait also provide any assurance of
compliance with this principle in actual life? I believe that the
answers to all these questions are affirmative, as I shall attempt
to demonstrate later in this paper.
(b) "Significance" and Mortality. My next account and
defense of the motive of self transcendence is based upon the
universal human awareness of physical mortality. As philosophers
have noted and commented upon for centuries, the price that each
person must pay for his rationality and self-consciousness is a
knowledge that he too must die.
Surely I need not argue that the finitude of human life is a
source of much preoccupation and regret. A myriad of religious
doctrines and philosophical systems have been devised to offer hope,
consolation, or at least perspective in the face of this common
fate. However, there is one response to the awareness of mortality
that is of considerable importance to our analysis. I refer to the
investment and devotion of time, talent, concern, loyalty, and
substance in behalf of enduring and permanent causes, ideals, and
institutions. Now there are, of course, many motives for these kinds
of activities. Prominent among these, however, is the desire to
extend the term of one's influence and significance well beyond the
term of one's lifetime -- a desire evident in arrangements for
posthumous publications, in bequests and wills, in perpetual trusts
(such as the Nobel Prize), and so forth. In all this, and more, we
find clear manifestation of a will to transcend the limits of
personal mortality by extending one's self and influence into
things, associations, and ideals that endure. This is, I suggest, a
profound and universal sentiment of which the parties in the
original position would surely be aware in their deliberations
concerning just provision for the future.16
(c) The Self and Society. If "self transcendence" is to
qualify as a primary good in Rawls's system, and not as a "take it
or leave it" personal good (that may or may not be adopted in a
particular "rational life plan" beyond the original position) then
it must be shown that the desire for self- transcendence is
essential to the very nature of a functioning human self. A strong
case for this position may be found in the writings of George
Herbert Mead and John Dewey.17 Mead suggests, in effect,
that the notion of a totally isolated self is a virtual
contradiction. The self, he argues, has its origin, nurture,
and sustenance in social acts. Furthermore, says Mead, the mind
emerges through the acquisition, in social acts, of communication
skills and the consequent absorption of the medium of "significant
symbols" known as language. Accordingly, the self is
defined and identified (i.e., "self conscious") only in terms of
social experience and the consequent perception of a "generalized
other" (or, roughly speaking, internalized norms or "conscience").
Moreover, even in moments of solitary reflection, the mind employs,
in silent soliloquy, the fund of meanings (i.e., the language) of
the community. The upshot of the position of Mead and Dewey would
seem to be that the self, by its very origin and nature,
transcends the physical locus (of body, of sense impressions, and of
behavior) which identifies the individual. "Self transcendence"
becomes, then, not a moral desideratum, but a basic fact of the
human condition.
Accordingly, "self transcendence" is not a more-or-less
occasional and accidental characteristic of individuals and
cultures. It is a consequence of universal conditions and
circumstances of human development. A sense and expression of self
transcendence is thus as necessary for mental health as is exercise
for physical health. Accordingly, the parties in the original
position would thus desire the opportunity to express and manifest
self transcendence, whatever else they might desire. Self
transcendence, in other words, is a primary good. Rawls, it
is worth noting, virtually endorses Mead's and Dewey's view of "the
genesis of the self" late in his book. (468-9)18
(d) Alienation: The Self Alone. If, as I have urged, self
transcendent concern is essential to well-being, then surely its
absence should be seen to exact a high price in the life quality of
those who are devoid of self-transcendent interests and concerns.
And here, I think, we find clear clinical evidence to support the
claim that self-transcendent concern is essential to psychological
health and well-being. In psychiatric and sociological literature a
lack of self transcending interest, concern and involvement due to
an incapacity to value external things in and for themselves is
called "alienation" -- a common and apparently increasing phenomenon
in contemporary life.19
The prominence of alienation in contemporary industrialized
society is due, in large part, to the individual's loss of control
over the social, economic, and political forces that determine his
destiny. With loss of control comes indifference and apathy. Because
in his social and vocational contacts one is responded to ever more
in terms of his functions, and ever less in terms of his
unique personality, he becomes estranged from the wellsprings of his
own unique personal being. He becomes, that is, alienated from himself. He is left aimless, vulnerable, insignificant,
solitary, and finite. In such a condition one loses not only his
self-respect; even worse, one is hard-pressed to recognize and
define the identity of his own self.
Surely alienation is the very antithesis of self- transcendence.
Within such a state there is no feeling of a personal contribution
to grand projects, no sense of involvement in significant events, no
investment and expansion of one's self and substance into enduring
causes and institutions. Surrounded by institutions, machines,
individuals, social trends for which one has no significance and to
which one can thus "transfer" no "import," one truly lives in an
"alien" world. Surely alienation is a dreadful condition, made
nonetheless so by its widespread and growing manifestations.
In the original position, the parties would have general
knowledge of the causes and symptoms of alienation. They would also
understand the direct threat of alienation to the primary good of
self respect. It follows that the parties would devise principles of
justice that would insure ample opportunities to identify with, and
to work for the sustenance and improvement of, just institutions in
their own time and in the future. Their chosen principles of
justice, in other words, would reflect the universal need to protect
and to enhance self respect through self transcendence.
The Paradox of Morality. Throughout these explorations of
the putative "need for self transcendence," we have found
indications of what is often called "the paradox of morality."
Briefly, the paradox is found in the common circumstances that one
lives best for oneself when one lives for the sake of others. Thus
stated, the rule seems pious and banal. Even so, it points to a
profound and recurring theme in religion and moral philosophy, a
theme that is especially prominent in the writings of contract
theorists from Hobbes to Rawls. Surely Rawls's theory of justice
argues forcefully that a group of self-interested egoists would,
from an initial position of equality and fairness, formulate and
accept rules of mutual regulation, assistance, and forbearance. (Cf.
Rawls, Chapter 1, and also p. 550). Other statements of the moral
paradox are abundant in the writings of contemporary philosophers.20
"The moral paradox," then, supplies still another argument for
self transcendence. But it is an argument with a difference. In our
earlier discussion of the motive for self transcendence, we adopted
a psychological approach; i.e., we considered the need for self
transcendence from the perspective of its origin and sustenance in
human experience and behavior. In contrast, the argument from the
moral paradox recommends self transcendence (in the form of
"the moral point of view") as a more prudential policy for achieving
self-enrichment and personal satisfaction. We will have further
occasion to refer to the moral paradox and its application to the
posterity problem.21
Rawls and "Self Transcendence." Would Rawls endorse this
account of the need for "self transcendence"? Not only would
he do so, it seems to me that he does, at times quite
explicitly. Rather than engage in a prolonged exercise in Rawlsian
exegesis, I will cite briefly just two of these endorsements. For,
while the primary good of self transcendence can be quite
effectively presented and defended on independent grounds, if we can
further indicate that Rawls's ideas concerning moral psychology are
congenial with, and supportive of, the notion of self transcendence,
then we may plausibly propose that an explicit statement of this
concept be imported into his general theory of justice as a
motivation condition in the original position.
Case One: "The Sense of Justice." In his eloquent development and
explication of "the sense of justice " (Chapter VIII), Rawls states
quite clearly that this sense, and the moral sentiments that follow
therefrom, are fundamental traits of the human condition.
A person who lacks a sense of justice, and who would
never act as justice requires except as self interest and
expediency prompt . . . lacks certain natural attitudes and
moral feelings of a particularly elementary kind. Put
another way, one who lacks a sense of justice lacks certain
fundamental attitudes and capacities included under the
notion of humanity.(488-9)
Rawls then points out that having a sense of justice necessarily
makes one liable to suffer the moral feelings of guilt and shame
should his behavior fall short of just expectations. However, "this
liability is the price of love and trust, of friendship and
affection, and of a devotion to institutions and traditions from
which [one has] benefited and which serve the general interest of
mankind." (489)
In this final sentence, is not Rawls affirming that a sense of
justice entails self transcendence, in the form of "love,
trust, friendship, affection," and, most significantly for our
purposes, "a devotion to institutions and traditions from which [one
has] benefited"? Is not this devotion expressed in a concern for the
well-being and preservation of these institutions and traditions for
their own sake and beyond the term of one's own lifetime? By saying
that one wishes to avoid the guilt and shame of failing to support
just institutions and ideals, is he not saying that one has a need
to transcend a total preoccupation with his immediate and personal
needs and desires? I suggest that Rawls's analysis of the sense of
justice implies affirmative answers to these questions. To have
a sense of justice is to have a self transcending concern for the
well-being and endurance of just associations, institutions, and
ideals for their own sakes.
Case Two: "The Idea of Social Union." Another indication of
Rawls's support for the concept of self transcendence is to be found
in his analysis of "the idea of social union." (#79) Here he expands
upon his crucial notion that it is the function of systems of
justice to maximize expectations of advantage and to adjudicate
conflicts within a society. (4) Of special interest to us, however,
is Rawls's often reiterated belief that social activities (i.e.,
"the social union") necessarily lead the normal, well-functioning
individual to extend his self interest toward an identification with
community interests, institutional interests, and ideal interests.
Thus, writes Rawls, "the members of a community participate in one
another's nature. . . the self is realized in the activities of many
selves." (565) And in a passage that is a virtual affirmation of the
principle of self transcendence, Rawls writes:
Human beings have in fact shared final ends and they
value their common institutions and activities as good in
themselves. We need one another as partners in ways of
life that are engaged in for their own sake, and the
successes and enjoyments of others are necessary for and
complementary to our own good. (522-3. My italics).
Accordingly, "only in a social union is the individual complete."
(525n) The good, to the individual, of participating in a well-
ordered social union follows, says Rawls, from "the psychological
features of our nature." (571) The self, that is to say, "is
realized in the activities of many others." (565) Thus Rawls seems,
in effect, to be stating here that a well-functioning human
personality needs and actualizes an extension and transcendence of
itself into enduring projects, institutions, and ideals, perceived
to be valuable in themselves. If this is a fair and accurate
paraphrase of Rawls's intention, then, once, again, he has affirmed
the need for self transcendence.
There are still more indications in A Theory of Justice
that Rawls might readily recognize "self transcendence" as a primary
good. However, these few will have to suffice.22
V
Self Transcendence as a Primary Good. A brief dialectical
exercise might help us to locate the place of self transcendence in
the index of primary goods, if it is to have a place at all. The
list of primary goods, we will recall, is divided into two basic
categories; the "natural" and the "social." Because self
transcendence has its origins in, and is directed to, social
phenomena, it seems obvious that it would belong in the latter
category. Among the social primary goods are found "rights and
liberties, powers and opportunities, income and wealth" (62) and
self respect. Might self transcendence be subsumed under one of
these goods, or must we suggest that it be added on as an additional primary good, which was carelessly overlooked by
Rawls? Fortunately, we can adopt the simpler course of including it
under an existing primary good, that of self respect which,
says Rawls, may be the most important social primary good. (396)
According to Rawls, to be properly included among the primary
goods a trait must (a) be fundamental to human nature, (b) be
desired "whatever else might be desired," and (c) found to be
indispensable to the fulfillment of a desirable and satisfactory
life plan. If, on the other hand, a trait is found to be
dispensable, or if acceptable substitution or compensation can be
found for a deprivation thereof, a trait cannot qualify as a primary
good.
How does self transcendence fare against these criteria? Quite
well, I believe. Consider first the question: "Is self transcendence
fundamental to human nature?" If my exposition has been sound, then
according to Mead's theory of the evolution of the self, the need
for social effect and identification is a necessary and inalienable
aspect of selfhood. In presenting the "law of import transference" I
have suggested that self transcendence is based upon a fundamental
and universal psychological phenomenon. Examples of this law are, I
submit, commonplace in our personal lives and in the records of
human culture.
Next, let us ask: "Is self transcendence indispensable to a
satisfactory life?" I believe that it is. Even great wealth cannot
compensate for deep-rooted alienation. Indeed, familiar examples, in
fact and fiction, of misery amidst wealth might be seen to describe
alienation, often caused by the wealth itself. Thus, if alienation
is understood in the original position to be a symptom of the
failure of the self to identify with and be connected to
transcending projects and ideals, and if alienation is further
perceived to be incompatible with the formulation of a satisfactory
life plan, the parties would include self transcendence, the remedy
of alienation, in the index of primary goods. It would be
acknowledged, that is to say, as a good to be desired, "whatever
else might be desired."
Self Transcendence and Self Respect. Before we turn
directly to the question of the relationship of self transcendence
to self respect, it may be useful to briefly review Rawls's account
of self respect. Rawls, we may recall, views self respect (or self
esteem) as having two aspects. The first is a person's sense of his
own value and "his secure conviction that his conception of his
good, his plan of life, is worth carrying out." The second aspect of
self respect "implies a confidence in one's ability, so far as it is
within one's power, to fulfill one's intentions. When we feel that
our plans are of little value, we cannot pursue them with pleasure
or take delight in their execution." (440) Thus, Rawls concludes,
without self respect, "nothing may seem worth doing, or if some
things have value for us, we lack the will to strive for them. All
desire and activity becomes empty and vain, and we sink into apathy
and cynicism." (440) Viewed positively, Rawls contends that "self
respect is not so much a part of any rational plan of life as the
sense that one's plan is worth carrying out." (178) For reasons such
as these, says Rawls, "the parties in the original position would
wish to avoid at almost any cost the social conditions that
undermine self respect." (440)
Rawls could scarcely have stated a stronger case for avoiding the
psychological condition of alienation. As described earlier,
personal self alienation is clearly indicated by the feeling that,
in Rawls's words, "nothing is worth doing," that one is powerless,
that one's "plans are of little value" and cannot be "pursued with
pleasure." These feelings of insignificance and isolation, I have
suggested, simply describe the absence of self transcending
projects, concerns, and interests. Indeed, so fundamental is self
transcendence to self respect that its opposite, alienation, is not
simply destructive of self esteem, it is destructive to the
very self "itself." When, in Erich Fromm's words, the
individual is no longer "the center of his world" and "the creator
of his own acts" he loses sight of his self identity -- the very
essence of his being.23 Clearly, then, an active
involvement in a world of cherished persons, honored ideals,
respected institutions and enduring causes, which is to say a
projection into and an identification with transcending entities and
projects, all this is a sufficient antidote to alienation.
Thus, if it is not too simplistic to say that alienation is the absence of self transcendence, and that alienation is
incompatible with self respect, then it follows that self
transcendence is a necessary condition for the achievement of the
primary good of self respect.
I suggest that this conclusion is reinforced by our other
findings concerning the bases of the need for self transcendence.
Thus, in my earlier discussion of the development of the self, the
psychological trait of "import transference" and the awareness of
personal mortality, I have indicated that the self finds its own
identity and value in involvements and concerns beyond itself, which
is to say through its own transcendence. Without
recapitulating these now familiar points, I believe that we can
conclude from our earlier discussion that the self can find no
source of abiding esteem totally from within. Transcendent
involvement and concern with projects, ideals, persons and
institutions beyond the self is necessary for self respect.
Accordingly, we have arrived at our desired conclusion: Self
transcendence is necessary for self respect and thus, by
implication, is a primary good.
Very well, if "self transcendence" qualifies as a primary good,
have we secured a practical principle of justice between
generations? Alas, we have not. There is still work to be done -- in
the original position. However, we have, hopefully, supplied the
needed "motivation assumption" with which such a principle might be
derived. Moreover, unlike Rawls's candidate assumption ("the heads
of families condition"), our motivation concept meets the necessary
criteria that we detailed earlier [final paragraph of Section III].
Namely, (a) it is neutral with respect to time (cf. Rawls, #45); (b)
it is applicable to all moral personalities (i.e., it is
"universal"); (c) it neither favors nor disadvantages identifiable
particular persons (i.e., it is "general"); (d) it is a primary
good, and thus is appropriately admitted into the deliberations of
the original position.
From "Just Savings" to "Just Provision". It follows from
the above criteria that the parties of the original position may
adopt a principle (unlike Rawls's principle of "just savings") that
will not necessarily favor immediately succeeding generations
at the expense of remote generations.24 Rawls's concept
of just savings," it should be noted, calls for "savings" of "the
gains of culture," "just institutions," and "real capital" (e.g.,
buildings and machines, etc.). (285, 288) This is fine, as far as it
goes. However, as I have argued elsewhere, some significant aspects
of "justice between generations" are not included within this
concept.25 For example: (a) "just anticipations" (i.e.,
careful and deliberate study of long-range impacts of proposed
policies); (b) "just forbearances" from ultimately harmful
activities and policies; and (c) "just stewardship" of an ongoing
and flourishing ecosystem. I would include all of these
dimensions in my broader conception of "justice between
generations," which, in this paper and elsewhere, I call "just
provision."
VI
Just Provision as an Abstract Principle of Justice. My
criticism of Rawls's position concerning justice between generations
is now essentially complete. So too is the development and
presentation of my own assumptions, concepts, and analytic tools.
Following a brief inventory of the relevant available information,
assumptions, and critical methods, we will assume the perspective of
the parties in the original position and attempt, on the basis of
this data and perspective, to derive new principles of just
provision for posterity, or at least to determine if such an
enterprise might still be carried out in the context of justice as
fairness. This analysis from the original position will follow three
basic stages: (a) an examination of just provision as an abstract
principle of justice (VI); (b) an examination of the adequacy of
just provision as a practical principle (i.e., its stability)
(VII); and finally, (c) an assessment of the congruence of the
practical principle of just provision with the full theory of the
good (VIII).
Where are We? In our analysis of Rawls's argument for just
savings, we found that "the heads of families condition" violated
the general rules of the original position (i.e., the veil of
ignorance, and the generality and universality rules). In addition,
this condition appears to be an ad hoc addition to the
theory, with no discernible function in Rawls's system except
to affect the outcome of the posterity question. For these and other
reasons, we found the "heads of families" assumptions to be
untenable, and it was discarded.
Following that, I presented an alternative motivation assumption
(i.e., "the need for self transcendence") which, I trust, is both
consistent with the general conditions of the original position and
qualified for inclusion in the index of primary goods. We can now
present a case before the parties of the original position that is
simple, consistent with Rawls's general theoretical rules and
presuppositions, and free of ad hoc modifications. However,
while we now have a better case, we have not demonstrated that it is
a sound and convincing case. To carry this project to a satisfactory
and affirmative conclusion would require, at least, a careful
assessment of alternative policies of provision for the future and
an exposition and analysis of Rawls's difficult, technical, and
lengthy work on "risk assessment and aversion" (Rawls, #26-30),
topics that I have, happily, been able so far to by-pass. Since I
haven't the space to develop and include these conclusions, I will
be unable to supply a clear, explicit, well-founded principle of
just provision. Even so, I believe that we can take some significant
steps toward such a realization.
What, then, do we have to bring to this task? What are our
resources? They are considerable. First, we have (with the
few noted exceptions) all the general conditions of Rawls's original
position; namely, the constraints of the concept of right, the
circumstances of justice, the rules of acceptance and exclusion of
knowledge (the veil of ignorance), the primary goods the rules of
deliberation, etc.26 Second, we have a condition
in the original position which pertains particularly to the
posterity issue; i.e., generational ignorance. Third, we have
now the assumption that "self transcendence" is a primary good. With
these assumptions and procedures at hand, we can now ask: "How would
the parties of the original position deliberate concerning the issue
of justice between generations?" And, "what principles of justice
between generations would result from these deliberations?"
Toward an Abstract Principle of Just Provision: Two
Arguments. The parties of the original position might first seek an
abstract principle of just provision, with the understanding that
such a principle might have to be modified to allow for compliance in the circumstances of actual life in a well ordered
society. Such a modified principle would, according to our
terminology, be a "practical" principle of justice. Very well, given
the best possible case (i.e., with stability for the moment taken
for granted), how might the parties proceed to formulate and defend
a principle of just provision?
Consider, first, what might be called "the argument from self
transcendence." By this account, the parties in the original
position, by reviewing the index of primary goods, would find that
whatever principles they chose, they would have to insure the
security of their self respect in actual life. By examining the
conditions of self respect, they would further conclude that they
must, at all costs, protect their self esteem from the
self-diminishing and self-demeaning condition of alienation.
And since alienation can be construed as the absence of self
transcending interests, concerns, loyalties, and projects, they
would wish to assure that in actual life they might be identified
with, involved in, and concerned about, persons, places,
associations, institutions, and ideals outside themselves.
Furthermore, the parties will know (through admissible knowledge of
general psychology) that by investing concern for transcending
things and ideals, that is to say by "transferring import," such
objects, plans, associations, and ideals become intrinsic
goods, and the expectation of their endurance becomes a good for the
individual. It then follows that the parties will understand that in
actual life their self respect will be integrally tied to active
concern for enduring things, associations and ideals. Thus,
paradoxically, what they perceive to be the future course of events
beyond their own lifetimes becomes relevant to their own well-being
during their lifetimes. (This of course is a manifestation of
"the paradox of morality"). In short, the parties will understand
(a) that unless lasting objective things, projects, and ideals matter to
them, their lives will be empty and devoid of
self-esteem, and (b) that they cannot truly love or care for these
things, projects, and ideals unless they hope and plan for
the preservation and flourishing thereof long beyond the span of
their personal lifetimes. Self transcendence, then, as a necessary
component of the primary good of self respect, assures that the
parties of the original position will care, generally, about
the course of events beyond their lifetimes, and about the
availability, to future persons, of (unspecified) goods,
opportunities, excellences, etc.
Of course, the veil of ignorance forbids any knowledge in the
original position of particular personal goods and causes that the
parties might wish to protect and preserve. However, the parties
will know that whatever the goods and values they may cherish in
actual life, these goods can not be actualized without the
primary goods. Accordingly, the argument from self transcendence
entails that the parties will desire to assure the continued
availability of such prerequisite primary goods as basic resources,
health, intelligence, self respect, equal opportunity, and equal
liberty. Thus the argument from self transcendence has the
interesting side effect of reinforcing the principles of equal
liberty and equal opportunity. This manifest application of self
transcendence to other parts of Rawls's system lends support to the
notion and acquits it of the charge of being an ad hoc
hypothesis.
Another argument for an abstract principle of just provision is
also familiar to us. We might call it "the argument from the
loyalty of justice." Assume that the deliberations concerning
justice between generations appear late in the agenda of the
original position. If so, some content to the rules of just
provision becomes evident; namely, some prevailing conditions,
assumptions and prior conclusions of the original position. Now if
the parties themselves may be assumed to be subject to the
"law of import transference," (the "law" is, after all, a component
of the primary good of self transcendence), then the content of
their prior conclusions will be invested, by the parties themselves,
with intrinsic significance. The result of this transfer of import
within the original position is noteworthy: the parties become
motivated to adopt principles of justice between generations that
will insure the perpetuation of the (to them) valued principles of
justice among contemporaries. And what is required to perpetuate
these principles? Answer: The circumstances of justice (moderate
scarcity, mutual disinterest, etc.) and just institutions. In short,
the law of import transference motivates the parties to adopt
principles of just provision requiring that care be taken to
perpetuate the conditions and institutions which support justice.
And so, while particular personal goods can not be prescribed
for the benefit of future generations (due to the veil of
ignorance), the protection and perpetuation of general
circumstances, conditions, and rules of right might be accomplished
by an adoption of principles of just provision. Indeed, due to their
own primary good of self transcendence (in the form of
"import transference"), the parties would be motivated to do just
that. The motive of self transcendence in the original position thus
extends all rules of justice among contemporaries into the future.
Furthermore, it is an extension without limit. So long as there can
be moral personalities (i.e., persons with the capacity for a sense
of justice, and deserving of justice), there may be just
institutions, and the parties will wish these institutions to become
actual and to flourish.
Some Conclusions. Having considered two arguments from the
original position (by following the prescribed rules and procedures
thereof and avoiding the use of data excluded by the veil of
ignorance), we are prepared now to propose a "draft principle of
just provision:"
Act so that the availability of primary goods,
circumstances of justice, and just institutions to future
generations will be assured, consistent with the
preservation of the rights of the living to equal justice.
This may serve as a beginning, but it is
only a beginning,
since several qualifications are in order.
To begin, there is the question of the available knowledge and
the capacity to affect the future course of events. Now the parties
would surely understand that in actual life they would be neither
omniscient nor omnipotent and that these limitations would affect
their abilities to anticipate the needs of, and to provide for,
future generations. Their eventual principle of just provision
should reflect this.
Even with this restriction, our "draft principle" has a decidedly
utilitarian tone to it, and thus might be unacceptable to the
parties of a Rawlsian original position. For instance, the parties
might be concerned that they might find themselves members of a
generation of whom unreasonably high sacrifices might be demanded in
order to maximize advantages across several generations.27
Should there not, then, be a "utility floor" (similar to that
implied by the difference principle) below which a generation should
not be required to go in asking just provision for the future? It
would seem, from Rawls's point of view, that no generation should
have to reduce its expectations so severely that it moves from a
state of "moderate scarcity" to a condition of "acute scarcity,"
thus relinquishing the circumstances that support the special
conception of justice (and the primacy of equal liberty). But what
of lesser, yet still considerable, sacrifices? Rawls writes that
"each age is to do its fair share in achieving the conditions
necessary for just institutions and the fair value of liberty; but
beyond this more cannot be required." (298) But just what is
required of the living? What is a "fair share"? According to
what rules do we determine a fair contribution to the well-being of
future generations?
At this point we run out of the supporting data and assumptions
necessary to carry this inquiry forward. To proceed further, we
would, like Rawls, have to examine and assess strategies of
choice-with-uncertainty and of risk- aversion. (Cf. Rawls, #26-9).
In addition, to continue this line of inquiry, we would also need to
examine alternative modes of provision for the future and attempt to
devise rules for choosing among the menu of possible policies. In
order to contain the scope of this paper, I have chosen to omit
these difficult considerations.
Suffice it to say that in the interest of minimizing the risk to
their prospects in actual life, the parties would likely place a
limit upon the claims that (from the standpoint of actual life)
future generations might place upon their own. Thus they would not
allow utilitarian imperatives to mandate ruin for the present in
behalf of the future. Justice as fairness prescribes "fairness" to
all generations.
A Tentative Abstract Principle of Just Provision. We are
ready, then, to state our somewhat less than final "abstract
principle of just provision":
The generation of the living is to adopt and effect
policies of care and provision such that the availability of
primary goods, circumstances of justice, and just
institutions to future generations will be assured, subject
to the limitations of available knowledge and capability and
the limits of fair sacrifice.
VII
Just Provision as a Practical Principle of Justice. If our
abstract principle of just provision is to lead to a practical
principle, we must supply evidence that the principle would be
complied with in a well-ordered society; that is to say, that the
principle would be "stable." As we seek this evidence, we may or may
not find that the abstract principle will require modification
before it is found to be tenable as a practical principle of
justice. Fortunately, our earlier discussion of the need for self
transcendence will provide most of the evidence that we are looking
for.
The Motive for Compliance. To begin, I would like to adopt
a negative approach to the question of stability. Rawls, we will
recall, holds that a sense of justice makes one liable, in the
violation thereof, to the "moral sentiments" of guilt and shame.
Similarly, I have argued that a failure to identify with self
transcendent projects, causes, and ideals creates, or manifests,
feelings of alienation. We are therefore led to ask: What are
the consequences (in terms of shame, guilt, alienation, etc.) of a
failure to make just provision for future generations? (Recall that
consistent with Rawls's "full compliance" assumption we are
referring here to conditions in a well-ordered society. Furthermore,
I will accept for the sake of this argument Rawls's contention that
in a well-ordered society the sense of justice among contemporaries
is stable). The members of such a self- serving generation might
have to entertain such unpleasant consequences as these: (a) they
might have to live and die with the realization that future persons
would likely, and with good reason, look back upon and regard their
(presently) well-ordered but unproviding generation with resentment,
indignation, and contempt. (b) Presumably, the members of a
well-ordered but unproviding society would be mindful that their
fortunate condition was the result of a long, laborious historical
process of gradual moral progress; yet in the face of this
knowledge, they would willfully decline to be part of this just
historical community. Such an attitude would exact a high penalty in
terms of lost self esteem. This would, in turn, make them liable to
feelings of guilt and alienation. (c) It would clearly
follow from this that members of the unproviding generation would
experience the shame of falling far short of their capacity to act
as free and rational agents.28 Rawls has written:
The desire to act justly derives, in part from the desire
to express most fully what we are or can be, namely free and
equal rational beings with a liberty to choose. . . Acting
unjustly is acting in a manner that fails to express our
nature as a free and equal rational being. Such actions
therefore strike at our self respect, our sense of our own
worth, and the experience of this loss is shame. We have
acted as though we belonged to a lower order, as though we
were a creature whose first principles are decided by
natural contingencies. (256)
This awareness, I suggest, would exact a heavy cost in terms of
the self esteem of the improvident generation.
Finally, (d) those who failed to provide for the future might
attempt to rationalize this policy by arguing that they really had
no projects or institutions worth preserving. This remedy would
likely prove to be worse than the disorder which prompted it. Why?
Because such an excuse would entail the dreadful self-deprecating
admission that the activities and achievements of the generation,
and presumably of most members thereof, were meaningless,
insignificant, and transitory.
In light of the points developed earlier, the positive benefits
of complying with a principle of just provision now become quite
clear. I trust that a brief mention of these familiar benefits will
suffice. First, (a) self respect is enhanced by the
understanding that the results of one's labors and talents will
endure. This satisfaction follows, in part, from a hope and
expectation that these consequences of one's life career, and thus
oneself, will be appreciated in the future. (b) A knowledge that
"things that matter" will endure eases the pain of the universal
knowledge of personal physical mortality. (c) The desire to
actualize potentialities (What Rawls calls The Aristotelian
Principle)29 is manifested in the creation of things
(e.g., art objects, scientific theories, literary works,
philosophical systems, etc.) of ever-greater subtlety and
complexity. Just provision allows for further advance in projects to
which one has contributed his work, skill and intellect.
Consequently, one is less inclined to feel that all his efforts and
skill devoted to the advancement of his chosen art, science or
craft, "are for nothing." This leads us directly to the next point:
(d) According to the law of import transference, things, places,
institutions, and ideals valuable to persons are valued for
themselves. The principle of just provision adds assurance that intrinsic goods will endure, which is, in turn, a good to
persons who value these intrinsic goods (i.e., who have transferred
import to these things). (e) Persons who act in behalf of posterity
display their capacity and desire to act rationally and
autonomously; i.e., they "express most fully what [they] can be,
namely, free and equal rational beings with a liberty to choose."
(256) Finally, (f) those who plan and act from interest and concern
for future persons feel that they are part of an historical
moral-community- in-time (or "social union"); that they are part of
a scheme, the significance of which transcends immediate time and
circumstance.30
For reasons such as these, I would suggest that members of a
well-ordered society, having a sense of justice toward each other
and motivated by a need for self transcendence, would also be
strongly motivated to provide for the future. This motive would be
sufficient to prompt them to adopt and to act according to a
principle of just provision. Furthermore, I suggest (but I will not
immediately attempt to prove) that this motive for compliance is
strong enough that our abstract principle of just provision might be
accepted, virtually intact, as a practical principle of
justice between generations.
This does not, however, complete our task. For even if we
eventually find warrant to believe that our abstract principle of
just provision would be complied with, we have yet to demonstrate
that such compliance would be a personal good. In other words, I
have not proven that this principle of right is congruent
with a rational person's good. This will be our task in the next
section. As we examine therein the congruence of a principle
of just provision with a rational person's good, we will encounter
further indication of strong motivation for compliance with the
abstract principle of just provision -- i.e., further reason to
adopt that principle as a practical principle as well.
VIII
"Congruence:" What is at Issue? Recall, for a moment, the
basic structure of Rawls's theory. Stated briefly, the order of
priority is as follows: First, the index of primary goods (derived
and explicated through the thin theory of the good) serves as a
premise in the formal derivation (in the original position) of the
principles of justice. The primary goods, we will recall, are those
natural and social goods that any rational person would desire,
whatever else he might desire. The principles of justice, in turn,
"constrain" the full theory of the good, which defines and
determines personal goods, moral virtues, and social values. This
means that nothing which violates the right can count as a
("full") good. But while the principles of justice (i.e., social
right) set the bounds of the ("full") good, they do not determine
the content thereof. The content is derived as the individual works
out his own "rational plan of life."
Now the question of congruence is simply this: Is the ("full")
good (i.e., a rational life-plan, etc.) consistent with justice?
Even more, are they mutually supportive? Stated thus, alongside the
previous paragraph, these questions may appear to be logical
nullities; i.e., by stipulation, goodness and justice must be
consistent. Fortunately, there is more to it than this. Rawls also
offers an independent definition of the good for a person; namely,
the successful pursuit of a "rational plan of life." This definition
is applied, in turn, to the definition of "moral virtue" (having
qualities that it would be rational to want in one's fellow
citizens). With the independent definition of good at hand, the
question of congruence is "opened." We can, like Thrasymachus in
Plato's Republic, ask if it is to one's personal advantage to
be just. As Rawls puts it: "It remains to be shown that this
disposition to take up and to be guided by the standpoint of justice
accords with the individual's good." (567)31 The question
of congruence, by the way, can be viewed from the perspective both
of justice and goodness. Thus we may ask, on the one hand, does "a
person's rational plan of life affirm and support his sense of
justice?" Conversely, we may ask "do the various desiderata of a
well ordered [i.e., just] society and . . . its just arrangements
contribute to the good of its members?" (513)
Now it follows from all this that a "principle of just provision"
for the future must be seen (in fact, and not by definition) to be
congruent with the good ("rational life plans") if it is to be a
genuine principle of justice. In other words, it must be shown that
no bonafide rational life plan can violate the principle of
just provision. Viewed positively, by asking whether just provision
is congruent with the good of a person in a well-ordered society, we
are asking: (a) would a person seeking to make just provision for
future generations be seeking that which would contribute to a
"rational plan of life" for himself? (b) is a personal disposition
to make just provision for the future the sort of quality that it is
rational for a person to want in his associates? In other words, is
just provision a moral virtue? Finally, (c) are the qualities
of a community with active policies of just provision the sort of
qualities that it is rational for a person to desire in his society?
In other words, is a policy of just provision a social value to
living members of that society?
I believe that just provision can be shown to be congruent with
all three senses of the good. Furthermore, this claim of congruence
may be supported with material developed earlier in this paper. I
will not attempt an extensive and multifaceted argument in support
of the congruence of just provision and personal good, since such an
exercise would involve a tedious recapitulation of familiar ideas.
Instead, I will assume that the foregoing account of (a) the justice of fair provision for the future and (b) the (personal
and social) good of caring for unborn generations offers
abundant supporting arguments in favor of congruence. I cannot from
this perspective conceive of any clear inconsistency between (a)
this principle of justice, and (b) these traits of goodness. But
while I will not present a full and detailed case for congruence,
some suggestive fragments of such an argument might be illuminating.
Why, then, might we believe that a person's good is congruent
with the principle of just provision? If our foregoing analysis of
the bases and nature of self transcendence are correct, it would
seem that no person would rationally choose (i.e., choose with
sufficient knowledge and "deliberate rationality") a life plan that
is without transcending meaning and direction and unproductive of
results of lasting significance. The principles of moral psychology
suggest that such a life, pursued wholly for oneself and thus with
total indifference as to its effects beyond one's lifetime, would be
empty, meaningless, and the source of self-contempt, shame, guilt
and alienation. Why, conversely, might we conclude that the
principle of just provision is congruent with personal good? As
noted earlier [the penultimate par. of #IV], a just society is a
"union of social unions" in which the good of each is
enhanced and amplified through the cooperative effort of all.
Accordingly, just institutions, functioning in behalf of future
generations, offer the means through which the individual's personal
need for self transcendence can become effective and actualized. By
pooling his talents and efforts with others, in a just "social
union" of complementary roles, the individual may find that his
contributions in behalf of posterity (and responsive to his need for
self transcendence) will be far more effective and lasting than they
would be had he attempted to express his "just concern" for
posterity on his own. In this sense, institutionalized just
provision in a well ordered society can be seen to be congruent with
the personal good of expressing self transcendence through an
effective caring for posterity.
In general, our findings indicate that the person whose plan of
life is responsive to his most basic human needs will desire to
perceive himself as a contributing member of an inclusive
community-in-time. Accordingly, he will be motivated to act, in the
course of his lifetime, in behalf of future persons. Stated simply,
caring for the future is a personal good. Furthermore, those
qualities in his associates that enhance his plans to enrich the
life of posterity will be perceived to be moral qualities, or
"virtues." Finally, those just institutions of society that
promote, exemplify, and amplify his efforts in behalf of the future
will display, in their just provision, a consistency with and a
complementation to, his personal good of self transcendence. In
other words, these institutions, by endorsing and acting out the
principle of just provision, will be congruent with his individual
good.
Stability, Congruence, and "The Moral Paradox." While
stressing the (congruent) good of seeking just provision for the
future, we must not lose sight of the principle of "the moral
paradox." Stated briefly, the paradox holds that one's personal
interest is best served by serving others or, at least, by serving
objective ends.32 By applying this paradox to the issue
of the duty to posterity we understand that one might best satisfy
the need for self transcendence not by seeking it directly but
through a genuine identification with and a concern for
transcending projects, institutions and ideals. Accordingly, a
practical principle of just provision might "serve" the living best
if it is explicitly oriented toward the benefit of future persons.
Paradoxically, if a principle of just provision betrays ulterior
personal interest of the living, then the benefits to the living may
be compromised. To paraphrase the scripture: "That generation which
loses itself in just concern for the future of its community, shall
find its good in self esteem, vigorous purpose, and transcending
significance." Like all such epigrams, this one suffers from
over-simplicity and pious generality. Even so, it serves as a brief
summary of some of the key findings of this paper, and of the
promise of the quest for self transcendence.
With this finding we have arrived, at last, at an answer to the
cynical challenge: "What do I owe posterity; after all, what has
posterity ever done for me?" Our duty to posterity is not
of the form of an obligation; that is to say, it is not a
contractual agreement to exchange favors. To be sure, posterity does
not actually exist now. Even so, in a strangely abstract and
metaphorical sense, posterity may extend profound favors for the
living. For posterity exists as an idea, a potentiality, and
as a valid object of transpersonal devotion, concern, purpose, and
commitment. Without this idea and potentiality, our lives would be
confined, empty, bleak, pointless, and morally impoverished. In
acting for posterity's good we act for our own as well.
Paradoxically, we owe it to ourselves to be duty-bound to
posterity, in a manner which focuses upon future needs as well as
our own. By fulfilling our just duties to posterity we may earn and
enjoy posterity's favors, even now.33
If my analysis has been sound, this strange and profound
conclusion is supported by Rawls's general theory of justice,
unencumbered by the inconsistency and ad hoc modification of
the heads of families condition, and enriched by the motivation
assumption of self transcendence.
The Stability of the Principle of Just Provision: A
Summary. "The most stable conception of justice," says Rawls, will
presumably display the following three features: (a) it will be
"rooted not in abnegation but in affirmation of the self;" (b) it
will be "perspicuous with our reason;" and (c) it will be "congruent
with our good." (499)34 If this is so, then these
concluding sections constitute an argument for the stability of the
principle of just provision. In the first place, (a) our exposition
and analysis of the need for self transcendence clearly indicates
that the principle of just provision is "rooted not in abnegation
but in affirmation of the self." Furthermore, (b) our derivation of
the abstract principle of just provision demonstrates that
such a principle is "perspicuous with our reason," in that the
principle follows from rules of the original position which, as we
know, displays a model of "rational decision procedures." In
addition, (c) we have just completed an attempt to demonstrate that
the principle of just provision is congruent with personal
good. Finally, (d) we have, throughout these final sections,
examined some direct arguments in support of the stability of
the principle of just provision. If these various presentations have
been successful, we may conclude that the abstract principle
of just provision is stable; that is to say, it would
generate its own support and thus would be complied with in a
well-ordered society. Accordingly, the parties in the original
position would have warrant to adopt the abstract principle as a practical principle of justice between generations.
IX
"Justice as Fairness" and the Duty to Posterity.
Throughout this paper, I have assumed and utilized the general
features and methodology of Rawls's theory of justice, while
modifying his treatment of the particular question of "justice
between generations." I am mindful of many of the cogent criticisms
of Rawls's contractarian approach to justice; indeed, I find many of
these criticisms to be quite persuasive. However, I have not treated
these objections for the simple reason that if I had done so
(and still successfully defended Rawls against all critics), we
never could have begun our inquiry into the adequacy of Rawls's
defense of the "just savings principle" within the context of his
theory. I can only hope that through this exercise I may have
developed some concepts and insights (most prominently, "self
transcendence") that are relevant to the posterity issue and which
might survive fundamental revisions, or even an ultimate refutation,
of Rawls's theory of justice.
Beyond this, I should note that despite my disagreements with the
particulars of his argument for just savings, I find Rawls's
contractarian approach to be an intriguing device for articulating
and attempting to solve the issue of intergenerational justice. "The
Original Position" displays, for ready analysis and review, the
procedures of rational choice that lead to general principles of
justice. By including in the rules of the original position such
general conceptual constraints as universality, generality,
and the prohibition against time preference, Rawls allows future
persons to serve as virtual spokesmen for their own potential
interests. Thus, through this suggestive thought-experiment, some
very subtle and difficult ethical puzzles concerning our duties to
future persons are made more tractable.
Rawls's argument for justice between generations, whatever its
particular limitations and errors might be, has suggested a
promising and fruitful approach to the vitally important issue of
the duty to posterity. Judging from two decades of responses35
to A Theory of Justice, from both within and outside the
philosophical profession, both the contractarian approach to justice
and the issue of the duty to posterity have, as a result of Rawls's
efforts, become more prominent in scholarly writing, discussion, and
teaching. The question of the future is becoming ever more a part of
our deliberative present. Rawls has introduced a provocative
conception of justice into contemporary thought and has forcefully
raised the question of the duty of the living to their successors.
Surely, through his successful effort to restore to philosophical
discourse these recently neglected, yet enduring and substantive,
moral issues, John Rawls has ably and admirably fulfilled his
duty to posterity.
NOTES AND REFERENCES
1.
This paper is an
abridgment and revision of portions of the second half of my
doctoral dissertation, Rawls and the Duty to Posterity
(University of Utah, 1976). An earlier version was presented in July
1977 to a National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar at
the City University of New York. I am grateful to my colleagues in
the Seminar for their helpful discussion and comments, and
especially to Thomas Nagel, the Seminar Director, for his careful
and well-directed suggestions. And I gratefully acknowledge the
support of the NEH which allowed me the time to prepare this paper.
2.
All quotations from and
references to John Rawls's A Theory of Justice (Cambridge,
Mass: Harvard University Press, 1971) will be cited in parentheses
in the body of the paper.
3.
By "present time of entry
interpretation," Rawls apparently means simply that the
parties are, and understand themselves to be, contemporaries. Yet,
in this passage there seems to be more to it than this. Rawls
neither explicates the term nor offers explicit justification for
this interpretation -- though I will shortly suggest the missing
Rawlsian justification. (Clearly the tone of the italicized clause
indicates an earlier use of the phrase "present time of entry," and
an earlier argument to the effect that the parties know that they
belong to the same generation. However, after at least four careful
and complete readings, I have been unable to locate any such
passages in the preceding pages of A Theory of Justice). The
interpretation reappears near the close of the crucial section on
"justice between generations." (#44) These two passages contain
essentially all that Rawls has to say concerning "the present time
of entry interpretation." Several philosophers have registered some
annoyance with the sudden appearance of this cryptic term, among
them R. M. Hare, (who calls it "an opaque phrase that I have found
nowhere explained,") in Hare, "Rawls's Theory of Justice - II,"
Philosophical Quarterly 23:92 (July, 1973), 243), also Brian
Barry, The Liberal Theory of Justice (Oxford University,
1973) p. 131n, and Gregory Kavka, "Rawls on Average and Total
Utility," Philosophical Studies, V:27 (1975), pp. 250-1.
4.
Hare, op. cit, pp.
243-4.
5.
This construction of the
missing Rawlsian justification for the present time of entry
interpretation seems obvious and compelling. Yet, I must confess
that here I correct an error and oversight of seven years standing.
From the time I began work on my dissertation (1975), through a late
draft of this paper (1982), I found neither justification for, nor
significant implications of, the present time of entry
interpretation. (I am grateful to Elinore Partridge for helping me
to correct this error). Now I acknowledge both that Rawls is correct
to take this interpretation, and that it apparently leaves the
parties with no motives for savings unless additional
motivational factors are either added or acknowledged in the
original position. (140, 292-1) Rawls chooses to add such an
assumption, while, n the following, I claim to find such an
assumption present in the given conditions of the original position.
6.
This criterion states that
the parties "cannot enter into agreements that may have consequences
they cannot accept. They will avoid those that they can adhere to
only with great difficulty" (176).
7.
Like the passage dealing
with the "present time of entry interpretation," this paragraph
appears suddenly, briefly, and with little if any support for its
claims. The succeeding paragraph is involved with a separate issue.
Other features of this passage are puzzling or noteworthy: (a) "The
parties are thought of as representing continuing lines of claims."
(By whom? Themselves? The other parties? The reader? Rawls?). (b)
"We may think of the parties as heads of families," but this
is apparently not necessary. (Rawls, however, seems to regard the
parties as having this role). (c) Notice the tentativeness in this
passage: e.g., "are thought of," "we may think," or additionally,
"being, so to speak, deputies . . . ," etc. (d) The parties in the
original position should "care" about individuals in the next
generation. Yet "individuals" in remote generations are
necessarily indeterminate from the perspective of the present. (e)
Thus, presumably, provision for remote generations is accomplished
only through a sequence of "carings" for adjacent generations.
(Later, in pages 288-90, Rawls says this quite explicitly). See also
note 14, below.
8.
Kenneth Arrow can get us
off to an excellent start. The heads of families assumption, he
writes, "(1) . . . Introduces an element of altruism into the
original position; if we introduce family sentiments, why not others
(national, tribal)? And why not elements of envy? (2) One might like
a theory of justice in which the role of the family was derived
rather than primitive. In a re-examination of social institutions,
why should the family remain above scrutiny, its role being locked
into the original assumptions? (3) Anyway, the family argument for
saving has an implication that should be displayed and might be
questioned. Presumably the burden of saving should fall only on
those with children and perhaps in proportion to the number of
children. Since education and public construction are essentially
forms of saving, taxes to support them should fall only on those
with children. In the original position, this is just the sort of
contract that would be arrived at if the concern for the future were
based solely on family ties." Kenneth Arrow, "Some Ordinalist-Utilitarian
Notes on Rawls's Theory of Justice," The Journal of Philosophy,
LXX:9 (May 10, 1973), p. 261-2.
9.
To be perfectly fair, I
must note that Rawls does not insist that a person must be a family
head, but he does require that one have at least a quasi-parental
concern for the "well-being of some of those in the next generation,
it being presumed that their concern is for different individuals
in each case." 128-9 (My italics).
10.
Cf. Kenneth Arrow's
objection (3), quoted in note 8, above.
11.
In order to save space, I
have reluctantly set aside consideration of still another objection
to the "heads of families" condition. Rawls argues that once the
"heads of families" in the original position choose their principle
of just savings for the next generation, the needs of remote
generations will be accounted for as well, through a line of
transfers along the intervening generations. (289-90) It is all too
easy to find refuting cases among current events and issues. For
example: (a) the issue of the use of chloro-fluorocarbons, and the
resulting depletion of stratospheric ozone; (b) the proliferation of
nuclear fission power facilities and the attendant problem of
radioactive waste disposal; (c) the prediction of "The Club or Rome"
study (in Limits to Growth, New York: Universe, 1972), and
other such forecasts, to the effect that a continuation of current
industrial practices will lead to economic and ecological collapse
and catastrophe in the next century. In all these cases, and many
more, the well-being of the present and immediately succeeding
generation might be secured at the cost of catastrophic long-term
consequences. Rawls's principle of just savings would apparently
allow such short-sighted policies. For still further objections to
Rawls's "heads of families condition," see Jane English's "Justice
Between Generations," Philosophical Studies, 31 (1977) pp.
91-104.
12.
In adopting the term
"self-transcendence," I emphatically disavow any theological or
metaphysical connotations that might be attached thereto. As I hope
the foregoing account will indicate, the term applies to a psychological concept which is to be interpreted and applied
naturalistically.
13.
My task is considerably
eased by the fact that I have published a more extended explication
and defense of the concept elsewhere. See my "Why Care About the
Future?" in Partridge, ed., Responsibilities to Future
Generations (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1981), pp. 203-220.
14.
Rawls is not, in this
case, referring directly to self-transcendence; rather, he is
speaking of the senses of justice. Later in this paper I will
attempt to show that the motive of self-transcendence is a basic
component of the sense of justice, and thus that Rawls could very
well be referring here to what I call self transcendence.
15.
Interestingly, the
conclusion of this "import transference argument" is about the same
as the conclusion which follows from the condition of generational
ignorance. However, since these are clearly separate arguments, the
claim that the parties would adopt such a principle is accordingly
strengthened.
16.
For an eloquent
expression of the sentiment to "transcend mortality," see Nicolai
Hartmann's "Love of the Remote" in his Ethics, Vol. 2: Moral
Values (New York: Macmillan, 1932). Portions reprinted in Partridge,
ed., Responsibilities to Future Generations, loc. cit.
17.
For an eloquent
expression of the sentiment to "transcend mortality," see Nicolai
Hartmann's "Love of the Remote" in his Ethics, Vol. 2: Moral
Values (New York: Macmillan, 1932). Portions reprinted in Partridge,
ed., Responsibilities to Future Generations, loc. cit.
18.
Rawls's account of the
development of "the morality of association" (#71) is a virtual
paraphrase of Mead's theory of the genesis of the self. Indeed,
Rawls cites Mead in the course of this argument. (468n) Perhaps,
then, we have found in this passage an endorsement by Rawls of one
of our independent arguments for the need for self transcendence.
19.
Eric and Mary Josephson
thus describe alienation: "Confused as to his place in the scheme of
a world growing each day closer yet more impersonal, more densely
populated yet in face-to-face relations more dehumanized; a world
appealing ever more widely for his concern and sympathy with unknown
masses of men, yet fundamentally alienating him even from his next
neighbor, today Western man has become mechanized, routinized, made
comfortable as an object; but in the profound sense displaced and
thrown off balance as a subjective creator and power." Eric and Mary
Josephson, eds., Man Alone: Alienation in Modern Society (New
York: Dell, 1962), pp. 10-1.
20.
Currently, this theme is
stressed by such "good reasons" philosophers as Kurt Baier, Kai
Nielsen, Marcus Singer and Stephen Toulmin. Cf. in particular, the
final chapter of Michael Scriven's, Primary Philosophy (New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1966). In a direct statement of the paradox,
Scriven writes:
Each citizen's chances of a satisfying life for himself
are increased by a process of conditioning all citizens not
to treat their own satisfaction as the most important goal.
Specifically, a system which inculcates genuine concern for
the welfare of others is, it will be argued, the most
effective system for increasing the welfare of each
individual. Put paradoxically, there are circumstances in
which one can give a selfish justification for
unselfishness. (240).
21.
The paradox is given its
most severe testing when it is applied to the question of the duty
to posterity. In such a case, the defenders of this duty might wish
to affirm that life is immediately enriched by the collective
agreement of the living to provide for the well-being of the unborn.
This is the position of the economist Kenneth Boulding:
Why should we not maximize the welfare of this generation
at the cost of posterity? Apres nous, le deluge has
been the motto of not insignificant numbers of human
societies. The only answer to this, as far as I can see, is
to point out that the welfare of the individual depends on
the extent to which he can identify himself with others, and
that the most satisfactory individual identity is that which
identifies not only with a community in space but also with
a community extending over time from the past into the
future. . . This whole problem is linked up with the much
larger one of the determinants of the morale, legitimacy,
and 'nerve' of a society, and there is a great deal of
historical evidence to suggest that a society which loses
its identity with posterity and which loses its positive
image of the future loses also its capacity to deal with
present problems and soon falls apart.
If I interpret Boulding correctly, he is saying, in effect, that
"we need the future, now." Kenneth Boulding, "The Economics of
Spaceship Earth," The Environmental Handbook, ed. Garrett
deBell (New York: Ballantine, 1970), pp. 99-100.
22.
In the next section, I
will argue that Rawls's analysis of "self respect" is directly
supportive of the primacy of self transcendence. (See Rawls #67).
Further support of "self transcendence" may be found (with varying
degrees of explicitness) in the third part of A Theory of Justice,
particularly in Rawls's discussion there of "The Aristotelian
Principle" (#65), "The Moral Sentiments" (e.g., self respect, guilt,
shame, etc.) (#67, #73), "Natural and Moral Attitudes" (e.g., "the
sense of justice") (#74), moral development (#40-2), "The Principles
of Moral Psychology" (#75), "The Idea of Social Union" (#79), and
"The Unity of the Self" (#85).
23.
Erich Fromm, "Alienation
Under Capitalism," The Sane Society. Reprinted in Man
Alone, ed. M. and E. Josephson (op. cit), p. 56.
24.
See note 11, above.
25.
Rawls and the Duty to
Posterity, loc. cit., ##41-2; also "Beyond Just Savings,"
unpublished colloquium paper presented at the annual meeting of the
Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association, San
Francisco, CA, March 24, 1978.
26.
These general conditions
of the original position are spelled out in the first half of
Chapter III (##20-25) of A Theory of Justice.
27.
As John Passmore has
indicated, we of the late twentieth century may well belong to such
a generation. (Man's Responsibility for Nature, p. 87).
28.
Here I am applying
Rawls's "Kantian Interpretation" of his theory of "Justice as
Fairness" (cf. #40 of A Theory of Justice).
29.
Cf. #56 of
A Theory of
Justice.
30.
Cf. #79 of
A Theory of
Justice.
31.
The sentence which
immediately follows indicates why we should be interested in this
question: "Whether these two points of view are congruent is likely
to be a crucial factor in determining stability." (567)
32.
Rawls expresses the
paradox (or more correctly, the subsidiary "hedonic paradox") in
this manner: "A person is happy then during those periods when he is
successfully carrying through a rational plan and he is with reason
confident that his efforts will come to fruition. He may be said to
approach blessedness to the extent that conditions are supremely
favorable and his life complete. Yet it does not follow that in
advancing a rational plan one is pursuing happiness, not at least as
this is normally meant. For one thing, happiness is not one aim
among others that we aspire to, but the fulfillment of the whole
design itself." (550)
33.
Here I borrow from my
"Why Care About the Future?", loc cit., pp. 217-8.
34.
For purposes of clarity
and continuity, I have re-arranged the order of these features. I
trust that this has not altered Rawls's meaning or intent.
35. This comment
apparently dates the last revision of this essay at the early 1990a.